Note:
the post below is out of date. The latest version can be found here.
Alternatively,
the latest version can
also
be downloaded from the links below:
Download
in .pdf format
Download
in .html format
Download
in .odt format
A
Moral Case Against Christianity
0)
Introduction and some terminology
1)
Preliminary issues
1.1) Moral
realism and theism
1.2)
The Bible and the sources of moral knowledge
1.3)
Sovereignty
1.4)
Who are we to judge God?
1.5)
Judging hypothetical characters
1.6)
Our sense of right and wrong and Christianity
1.7)
The Fall
1.8)
The Old Testament and Christianity
1.9)
Hell and Christianity
1.10)
Context
2)
Immoral laws and false moral claims in the Old Testament
2.1)
Women stoned to death for having sex before marriage
2.2)
Women and men burned to death for getting into an outlawed kind of
marriage
2.3)
Women burned to death for prostitution
2.4)
Men executed for having sex with other men
2.5)
Women and non-human animals executed for having inter-species sex
2.6)
Oxen stoned to death as a punishment
2.7)
An assortment of immoral commands and false moral claims
2.8)
The hardness of the hearts of the ancient Hebrews
3)
David's murder of Uriah, and the biblical god's immoral reaction
4)
Jesus and the biblical god
5)
Jesus and "family values"
6)
Hell
6.1)
Infinite Hell vs. finite Hell or no Hell
6.2)
Hell as a place of torment vs. Hell as some state of mind or state of
being
6.3)
Hell as imposed vs. Hell as chosen by the damned
6.4)
The evil of Hell
7)
Conclusion
Notes
and references
0) Introduction and some terminology
1)
In this article, I will make a case against Christianity based on the
actions of the biblical god, arguing that he isn't morally good, let
alone morally perfect.
2) I
will not define "Christianity", but will try to make this
case as broad as I can, in order to encompass nearly all if not all
religions that go by the name "Christianity".[1]
3) By "the biblical god" I mean the entity described in the
Bible, and who is claimed to be the creator.
There
are of course different versions of the Bible: Not only are there
different translations, but also different beliefs about which books
are inspired.
As I
mentioned before, I will try to make the case as broad as a can, in
order to encompass different versions.
4) By "God" I mean an omnipotent, omniscient, morally
perfect being, creator of all other beings.
Christians
usually claim that the biblical god is God, and also usually just say
"God" - they never say "biblical god", as far as
I know.
However,
when considering objections, and for the sake of clarity, I will
usually use the expression "biblical god" to make clear
what the objection actually consists in, even if Christians would say
"God", rather than "the biblical god".
5) By a "moral agent" I mean any being that has moral
properties, like being morally good, or morally evil, or something in
between, and/or whose actions are sometimes immoral, or morally good,
etc. For instance, nearly all adult humans are moral beings, whereas,
say, sharks are not.
6) All quotes of biblical passages are from the King James Version
(KJV).
I don't believe that the KJV is a good translation, but the passages
in question are similar in all mainstream versions, so this should
not be a problem.
7) When I talk about the actions of the biblical god, of course I'm
not actually claiming that he exists. I'm just taking into
consideration the actions as described by books Christianity claims
are inspired.
I
will give some more details on this point later.
8)
I
only refer to different parts of this article as "sections"
or "subsections" - i.e., no sub-subsections, etc., but I
think links between the relevant parts of the document will prevent
any ambiguity.
9) In order to be
thorough, I will consider a wide range of objections, whether
actually raised by Christian philosophers or by other Christians, or
even potential objections I think someone might raise.
I will, of course,
consider all the main objections to arguments of this kind.
10) As usual, I
don't claim that there is any novelty in the ideas on which I base
this case.
1)
Preliminary objections
In this section, I will address some objections that are or might be
raised to any moral case against Christianity, prior to actually
assessing the content of the particular objections.
1.1) Moral realism and theism
According
to some theist philosophers, if theism is not true, then neither is
moral realism.
I
don't think that their arguments succeed, but there is no need to
assess the claims here.
This
is a case against Christianity,
not against theism in general.
Moreover, since
Christianity entails moral realism, we may safely assume moral
realism when arguing against Christianity.
1.2) The Bible and the sources of moral
knowledge
Someone
might object that, without the Bible[2],
we have no reliable source of moral knowledge, and so we cannot
properly judge the actions of the biblical
god.
This is not an objection I'd expect serious philosophers to raise,
but I've seen some Christians making claims like this, so let's point
out that:
1) Most people in most civilizations did not have the Bible.
If they did not have any reliable source of moral knowledge, how
could the people in those civilizations be blamed for their actions?
How is was their fault that they, say, tortured or raped others, if
they did not have any reliable means of telling right from wrong?
Moreover, can non-theists from today's predominantly non-Christian
countries (e.g., China, Japan, Vietnam) be blamed for their actions?
Could Muslims who have not been exposed to Christianity be blamed for
following the teachings of Islam - including those cases in which
Islam and Christianity do not agree?
If those people can't be blamed for their actions, then they deserve
no punishment at all - and surely, no afterlife punishment, either.
But that contradicts most versions of Christianity.
2) In fact, most people today do not use the Bible as a source
of moral beliefs, since most people today aren't Christians.
Again, if they have no reliable source of moral knowledge without the
Bible, why should they adopt Christianity?
If there is no reliable source of moral knowledge without the Bible,
then it seems they have no reliable way of assessing whether the
Bible - rather than, say, the Quran - is a reliable source of moral
knowledge. How would that be their fault?
3) In fact, if there is no reliable source of moral knowledge without
the Bible, it seems plausible even without considering the Bible's
content that the Bible won't provide any such source, either.
For, how would Christians know that the Bible is a
reliable source of moral knowledge?
Even if they have good reasons to believe that it was inspired by a
powerful being, that would not give them any reasons to believe that
it was inspired by a morally good being.
And they can't reliably test whether the Bible contains moral truths
unless they have another means - say, a sense of right and wrong -
that can be used to make moral assessments, at least in a generally
reliable way.
1.3) Sovereignty
Another
objection might be that the creator is sovereign, and he has no moral
obligations.
Thus,
he wouldn't be acting immorally if he acted in some way - whatever
that way is.
That, however, seems utterly implausible.
If there is a creator that is a moral agent, and he tortures everyone
else for eternity just for fun, I think we could clearly say that
such creator is acting immorally.
If,
on the other hand, a creator is not a moral
agent, then he's neither morally good nor morally bad nor morally
anything, but then, Christianity is not true just because of that,
since Christianity claims that, say, Jesus is morally good.
Someone
might also claim that the biblical god is
God, and he's not morally good in the usual sense
of "morally good", but he's the source of goodness, and has
no moral obligations himself.
I think this suggestion has a lot of problems, but let's simplify the
matter:
If
someone claims that religion X is true, and religion X claims that
God tortures
everyone else for eternity just for fun, we can safely conclude that
religion X is not true because an entity who behaves in that way
would not be God -
since it would not be morally perfect.
And
if religion Y claimed that God
created
the universe just for the fun of watching the "show" of
limited sentient beings struggling, killing or being killed, etc.,
and does not care at all who or what suffers as long as he has fun,
we would be able to tell that such a religion is not true, since a
morally perfect being would not do that.
Similarly,
then, one can properly make a case against Christianity based on the
actions of the biblical god, as described
in the Bible.
Of course, the biblical god does not torture everyone for eternity
for fun - that would make the case too easy -, but that does not
prevent us to assess his actions.
Granted,
Christians will object to my assessments of the morality of the
biblical god's actions, but that would
require actually assessing the actions, not dismissing the whole
moral case against Christianity merely on the basis of "sovereignty"
- whatever that is.
1.4)
Who are we to
judge God?
Someone
might raise the objection that we're morally flawed, so we shouldn't
judge God.
Actually,
if we know that an entity is God,
we can easily judge his actions - and conclude that they're never
immoral, since God is morally perfect.
However,
I'm not making any claims about God,
but making moral assessments of the actions of the
biblical god,
as described by the Bible.
1.5)
Judging hypothetical
characters
While
this should go without saying, I've seen some odd objections, so I'd
like to point out that we can easily - and correctly - make moral
assessments about people in hypothetical scenarios, without being
committed to the existence of the people in question.
For
instance, we can say that something like "The fact that Lex
Luthor did such-and-such thing shows that he's not morally good",
and that would not normally be interpreted as a commitment to the
existence of Lex Luthor.
Rather,
we're just taking the perspective of the story, instead of stating
something like "If Lex Luthor existed and had acted in
such-and-such manner, then that would show that he wouldn't be
morally good", which would be more cumbersome.
I
will take a similar approach to the
biblical
god in
many cases, but I'm in no way suggesting that he exists.
I'm
not assuming that he does not exist, either.
Rather,
the point is that we can make a moral assessment of his actions - as
described by books Christianity holds are inspired -, regardless of
whether or not he exists.
1.6)
Our sense of right and wrong and Christianity
As
I explained in previous subsections, we can use our sense of right
and wrong to assess whether Christianity is true, by assessing the
morality of some of the actions of the biblical
god.
However,
someone might claim that even if my
sense
of right and wrong tells me that the biblical
god
is
not morally good - let alone morally perfect - their
sense
of right and wrong tells them otherwise.
Granted,
that might happen, but we have to assess the matter carefully before
concluding it does in a particular case.
For
instance, there are plenty of examples in which some Christians seem
to actually see moral problems in some of the actions of the biblical
god, so they come up with some way of trying to explain it away.
For
example, they might contend that people are in Hell by their own free
choice, so it's not the fault of the biblical
god. I
maintain that such
claims are untenable
-
i.e., people do not put themselves in Hell -, so the difference in
moral assessments might result from that.
Still,
if some Christians' sense of right and wrong actually yields a very
different verdict from mine when assessing the morality of the
actions of the biblical
god
that
I will consider, and in particular they find no fault in his actions,
then clearly they won't find the case I'm making persuasive at all.
All
I would ask from readers is to try to assess the actions in question
carefully, and reach their own conclusions.
1.7)
The Fall
Another
objection a Christian might raise against this moral case goes as
follows: As
a result of the Fall, we shouldn't trust our sense of right and wrong
to make negative assessments about the moral character of the
biblical
god,
or to conclude that he made false moral assessments.
A
sufficient reply to that objection is as follows:
First,
this objection seems to assume Christianity - including its moral
claims.
But
why should we assume that?
On
the contrary, we're assessing whether Christianity is true, so
assuming it would defeat the purpose of the assessment.
In
fact, someone accepting this objection would be essentially refusing
to use her moral sense as a means to assess whether Christianity is
true - for every negative assessment would be rejected out of hand -,
even if she claims that the biblical
god
is
morally good, apparently accepting her moral sense in those cases in
which it yields a positive assessment of the biblical
god
and
his actions.
Once
again, there is no good reason to refuse to use one's moral sense in
this particular case, given that we can use it in general, to assess
religious claims.
Second,
if we shouldn't even trust our moral sense even when it yields
crystal clear assessments[3],
like, say, that oxen
aren't moral agents,
or that a woman in ancient Israel who became a prostitute and was the
daughter of a priest, did not deserve to be burned
to death for
that, then that would cast such serious doubts on our moral sense
that it would be hard to see how any
moral
assessment would be justified, given that we're rejecting even
crystal clear ones.
The
Bible would not help, of course, since we would not be able to assess
that the biblical
god
is
morally good, either, or that the Bible is a guide to moral truth.
1.8)
The Old Testament and Christianity
Different
versions of Christianity have different views about the relation
between Christianity and the Old Testament, on issues ranging from
whether some stories should be interpreted literally, to even whether
the Old Testament is part of Christian scripture at all.
I
will consider such matters later, but for now, I will just point out
that versions of Christianity comprising most adherents seem to agree
that even though many or all of the laws of the Old Testament do not
apply to Christians, nevertheless they were laws given by the
biblical god -
who they claim is God -
to the ancient Hebrews.
1.9)
Hell and Christianity
As
in the case of the Old Testament, different versions of Christianity
have different views of Hell.
I
will address different variants later, but for now, I will point out
that versions of Christianity comprising most adherents hold that
there is indeed endless suffering - even if they do not agree on its
nature, who or what causes it, etc.
1.10)
Context
In
my experience, a more or less common objection to moral arguments
against Christianity contends that biblical quotes are taken out of
context, and that we should also consider those cases in which the
biblical
god does
something that's clearly good.
According
to this objection, if we were to take that into consideration, our
conclusion would be that the biblical
god is
morally good, and that if some of his actions appear not to be so,
it's because we don't have enough knowledge about the situation to
make a better assessment.
However,
with that criterion, someone might say that even if some of his
actions appear to be morally good, that's only because we don't have
enough information about the situation to conclude that they're not.
It
seems to me that both claims would not be warranted: it seems we do
have
enough information to make a moral assessment of the actions of
entities in hypothetical scenarios, in many cases, and the same
applies to the biblical god.
In
particular, if an action appears to be morally wrong, and all the
possible reasons that we can come up with fail to provide a
justification for said action, and further, there appear to be better
alternatives - less bad, or even not bad -, then it seems clear that
we're justified in assessing that such action would be morally wrong.
In
addition to that, in some cases, we even know the biblical
god's motivation - to punish people he claims deserve such
punishment, for instance -, and so a claim that he acted for
mysterious reasons appears to be untenable.
The
same goes, of course, for morally good actions.
However, I don't
think that it's in any way inappropriate not to also quote actions
that appear to be morally good.
Objecting
that I'm only focusing on the bad would be out of place: it would be
like saying that if I said that a dictator who tortured people to
death just for peacefully expressing disagreement with some of his
policies acted immorally, I would be taking things out of context
because the dictator in question, say, loved his children, and I did
not point that out.
Well,
maybe the dictator did love his children, but that does not change
the fact that he acted very immorally when he tortured people to
death just for peacefully expressing disagreement with some of his
policies.
Given
the extent of the immorality, my point that he's not morally good
would be accurate.
Still,
I will assess specific objections claiming that he may have had some
particular good reason when required.
2)
Immoral laws and false moral tenets in the Old Testament
In
this section, I will consider a number of commands given by the
biblical god in
the Old Testament, which clearly show that the biblical
god is
not morally good.
Unless
otherwise specified I will assume for the sake of the argument that
the commands come from the biblical god. One can reasonably make this
assumption in a moral case against Christianity, since the Bible is
inspired according to Christianity, and the Bible actually claims
that the commands were given by the biblical
god.
In
fact, the passages I will quote are, according to the Bible, either
the words of the biblical god
himself,
or the words of Moses, conveying the commands of the biblical
god.
Exodus
20: 22
And the LORD said unto Moses, Thus thou shalt say unto the children
of Israel, Ye have seen that I have talked with you from heaven.
Exodus
21: 1
Now these are the judgments which thou shalt set before them.
Leviticus
20:
1
And
the LORD spake unto Moses, saying,
Deuteronomy
1:
1
These be the words which Moses spake unto all Israel on this side
Jordan in the wilderness, in the plain over against the Red sea,
between Paran, and Tophel, and Laban, and Hazeroth, and Dizahab.
3 And it came to pass in the fortieth year, in
the eleventh month, on the first day of the month, that Moses spake
unto the children of Israel, according unto all that the LORD had
given him in commandment unto them;
Deuteronomy
12:28
Observe
and hear all these words which I command thee, that it may go well
with thee, and with thy children after thee for ever, when thou doest
that which is good and right in the sight of the LORD thy God.
Deuteronomy
13:18
When
thou shalt hearken to the voice of the LORD thy God, to keep all his
commandments which I command thee this day, to do that which is right
in the eyes of the LORD thy God.
Deuteronomy
18:
15
The LORD thy God will raise up unto thee a Prophet from the
midst of thee, of thy brethren, like unto me; unto him ye shall
hearken;
16 According to all that thou desiredst of the
LORD thy God in Horeb in the day of the assembly, saying, Let me not
hear again the voice of the LORD my God, neither let me see this
great fire any more, that I die not.
17 And the LORD said unto me, They have well
spoken that which they have spoken.
18 I will raise them up a Prophet from among
their brethren, like unto thee, and will put my words in his mouth;
and he shall speak unto them all that I shall command him.
19 And it shall come to pass, that whosoever
will not hearken unto my words which he shall speak in my name, I
will require it of him.
I
will later
consider
and objection to the claim that the passages under consideration are
inspired.
2.1)
Women stoned to death for having sex before marriage
Deuteronomy
22:
13 If any man take a wife, and go in unto her,
and hate her,
14 And give occasions of speech against her,
and bring up an evil name upon her, and say, I took this woman, and
when I came to her, I found her not a maid:
15
Then shall the father of the damsel, and her mother, take and bring
forth the tokens of the damsel's virginity unto the elders of the
city in the gate:
16
And the damsel's father shall say unto the elders, I gave my daughter
unto this man to wife, and he hateth her;
17
And, lo, he hath given occasions of speech against her, saying, I
found not thy daughter a maid; and yet these are the tokens of my
daughter's virginity. And they shall spread the cloth before the
elders of the city.
18
And the elders of that city shall take that man and chastise him;
19
And they shall amerce him in an
hundred shekels of silver, and give them unto the father of the
damsel, because he hath brought up an evil name upon a virgin of
Israel: and she shall be his wife; he may not put her away all his
days.
20 But if this thing be true, and the tokens of
virginity be not found for the damsel:
21 Then they shall bring out the damsel to the
door of her father's house, and the men of her city shall stone her
with stones that she die: because she hath wrought folly in Israel,
to play the whore in her father's house: so shalt thou put evil away
from among you.
So,
the biblical
god commanded that if a woman has sex and then gets married to
someone who doesn't know she's not a virgin, she is to be stoned
to death.
Moreover,
the biblical god
attempted
to justify the punishment, implying that she deserved to be stoned to
death because
she had sex before marriage and then married someone who did not know
that she wasn't a virgin, and apparently for prostituting herself at
her father's house - which may not even be true.
However,
it is clear that a woman does not deserve to be stoned
to death for
any of that. The same applies if the woman lived in ancient Israel.
So,
the biblical god both gave immoral commands, and made false moral
claims.[4]
Objection
2.1.1) The biblical god has sovereignty over life and death. He gives
life, and he has the right to take it. He does no wrong by calling
for the stoning of those women, and those following his orders do no
wrong, either.
Reply:
First,
there is no good reason to believe that he has the right to take
someone's life just because he created that person.
Second,
the biblical god is not saying that the non-virgin should be killed
because he says so and he has the right to take any life if he says
so.
Rather,
he falsely claims that she deserves to be stoned to death as a
punishment for her actions.
Third,
this command does not "only" involve taking her life.
It's
a command to torture
her to death. She's
not "only" to be killed; she's to be stoned
to death.
Objection
2.1.2) She deserves to be stoned to death not for having sex before
marriage at her father's house and then marrying someone who did not
know, but for disobeying a morally perfect creator.
Reply:
First,
that's not what the Bible says.
The
Bible implies that she deserves such a punishment because she had sex
before marriage and then married someone who did not know that she
wasn't a virgin, and apparently for prostituting herself at her
father's house - which may not even be true -, but not for disobeying
a morally perfect creator.
Second,
it should be obvious to a human being who is contemplating the matter
rationally that a morally good or morally perfect entity would not
command that a woman be stoned
to death for
having sex before marriage and then marrying someone who does not
know that she wasn't a virgin, and/or for prostituting herself.
Third,
actually, disobeying a morally perfect creator, on its own, does not
merit being
tortured to death.
Fourth,
actually, there are plenty of violations of the biblical law that are
not
punished
by death, let alone by torture to death.
One
such case is provided by the very Bible passage under consideration:
if a man falsely accuses his wife of not being a virgin when she
marries him, he is not to be tortured to death.
Instead,
he is to pay
a fine.
Other
versions of the Bible might include a more severe punishment for him
than a fine[5], but nothing comparable
to torture to death.
Moreover,
there are plenty of cases in which biblical law - in any versions -
establish punishments not involving either torture or death for those
who break the law.
Objection
2.1.3) She deserves to be stoned to death not for having sex before
marriage at her father's house and then marrying someone who did not
know, but for disobeying a morally perfect creator in the particular
case in which such a creator decides that the adequate punishment for
breaking his rules is to be tortured to death.
Reply:
This
objection is very similar to the previous
one,
and a similar reply applies:
First,
that's not what the Bible says.
The
Bible implies that she deserves such a punishment because she had sex
before marriage and then married someone who did not know that she
wasn't a virgin, and apparently for prostituting herself at her
father's house - which may not even be true -, but not for disobeying
a morally perfect creator.
Second,
it should be obvious that a morally good or morally perfect entity
would not command that a woman be stoned
to death for
having sex before marriage and then marrying someone who does not
know that she wasn't a virgin, and/or for prostituting herself.
Third,
actually, disobeying a morally perfect creator, on its own, does not
merit being
tortured to death.
Fourth,
with that criterion, someone might posit a religion in which a
morally perfect creator called "Todd" commands that those
who, say, eats pork, be tortured to death, but those who rape or
torture children for fun be forced to pay a small fine to the
parents, and nothing more.
The
point is that a morally perfect creator would not command either what
Todd commands in that example, or what the biblical
god commanded in the biblical story under consideration, and
claiming that the commanding entity is morally perfect is not a
rational way of trying to excuse his actions.
Objection
2.1.4) That command has to be considered in context, and the context
is given by the biblical god's covenant with Israel.
Reply:
Let's
take a look at the matter:
The
biblical god made a pact with some of the
leaders of Israel.
He
agreed to provide some kind of assistance in terms of food supplies,
sometimes military help, etc., and on the other hand he commanded
that they torture
to death any
woman who has premarital sex at her father's house, and then gets
married to someone who does not know that she's not a virgin.
Even
if the biblical god
always
did as agreed, it should once again be obvious that that would not
excuse his actions:
He
just agreed to provide some help with food and fighting, and then
demanded that some women be tortured to death, even though they
obviously did not deserve that.
On
top of that, he actually lied, by implying that they deserved to be
stoned to death.
So,
the covenant does not alter the assessment of his actions as immoral.
Objection
2.1.5) The
biblical god realized that the command under consideration, alongside
other harsh commands, was required to keep social peace among the
ancient Hebrews, who weren't ready for a better law. Their hearts
were hard.
Reply:
First,
this command wasn't merely "harsh"; it was profoundly
unjust. It was a command to stone
women to death if
they had sex before marriage and then married someone who didn't know
they weren't virgins.
Second,
the
biblical
god also
lied by implying
that they deserved to be stoned to death.
Third,
the biblical
god is
an entity of immense power, capable of and willing to intervene in
the history of Israel on many occasions.
Obviously,
he could have pointed out that those women did not deserve to be
stoned to death, instead of falsely claiming that they did and then
commanding that they be stoned.
No
social breakdown would have followed from
refraining
from making false moral claims and from issuing a profoundly unjust
command.
What
would the ancient Hebrews have done, if he had not lied and had not
commanded that they be stoned to death?
Rebel
against an all-powerful
being
because he does not command
them
to stone women to death for having premarital sex and then marrying
someone who does not know that they did?
Should
we believe that his commands
would
only be obeyed by most of the population if they were in line with
what the people he's giving commands to already wanted?
What
kind of command
is
that?
That
seems absurd.
And
if some of them absurdly would have rebelled against an all-powerful
being
for that, then so be it. The potential absurd rebellion of some of
the people who wanted to stone to death any woman who had sex before
marriage and then married someone who didn't know she wasn't a
virgin, does not justify giving the command that those evil people
wanted.
In
short: if some evil people would only "follow" certain evil
commands, that does not justify giving them the evil "commands"
that they want, and on top of that telling them or implying that
their actions were actually just.
So,
this objection is also unreasonable.
However,
even if - against
all reason -
we assume that there was some justification for calling for the
execution of those women, the biblical god could have always
commanded that they be killed in a way the minimizes suffering;
furthermore, he could have refrained from falsely implying that they
deserved to be stoned to death.
Instead,
he commanded that they be tortured to death by means of stoning -
again, not that it would be reasonable to assume that there was some
justification for calling for that execution -, and made false moral
claims against them.
Objection
2.1.6) Those
passages are allegorical. They should not be taken literally.
Reply:
Those
are commands,
and
moral
claims.
How can they be an allegory?
In
any case, there is nothing whatsoever in the text indicating that
those passages weren't literal.
If
the biblical god issued commands and made moral claims, he should
have expected that they would be taken literally, since that's how
commands and moral claims are usually taken, and that's how his
commands and moral claims were usually taken.
So,
if he did not mean for them to be taken literally, he should have
clarified that.
Furthermore,
if he made a mistake and expected the claims and commands not to be
taken literally, then when they were so taken - as any reasonable
person would take them -, and the claims were believed and the
commands followed - not reasonable anymore -, then the biblical
god should
have clarified that there had been a misunderstanding.
He
did not, so that would be on him even if he hadn't meant for them to
be taken literally - though, again, it seems clear that he did.
Objection
2.1.7) If
the biblical god wanted those harsh laws to be enacted, then why did
Jesus later chose to spare the adulterer?
Reply:
Stepping
out of the story for a moment, it seems that whoever wrote that story
about Jesus had a different agenda from whoever wrote the part of the
Old Testament under consideration, and probably very different moral
beliefs on the subject.
If
the story about Jesus' sparing a woman who had committed adultery is
true, then Jesus too had a different agenda from whoever wrote
Deuteronomy, and probably very different moral beliefs as well.
But
leaving that aside and going back to the events as described in the
Bible - and also leaving aside that the particular command under
consideration is not about adultery, but women who have premarital
sex, at least under certain circumstances -, we can point out that:
a)
The laws aren't just harsh, but profoundly unjust,
b)
Whatever the reasons for the biblical
god's
later change of heart, that does not excuse his previous commands and
lies, and,
c)
Some deeds of the biblical god described in the New Testament do not
appear to be better than any of those described in the Old Testament;
in fact, some of them are even a lot more
evil if
the interpretation that there is infinite hell is correct.
But
that's a matter for a later
section.
Objection
2.1.8) Those laws applied only to the Hebrews, but do not apply after
Jesus.
Reply:
That's
beside the point.
It
remains the case that the biblical
god
gave
immoral commands and made false moral claims, even if he only gave
such commands to some people, and only made such claims before some
people.
Objection
2.1.9) Those passages are not inspired. That wasn't the law given by
Jesus' father, but a law made by humans.
Reply:
Then,
why is it the case that nearly all versions of Christianity today
consider them to be inspired?
Why
did Jesus
himself not
point out that those laws were not the work of his father?
In
fact, what Jesus said was:
Luke
16:
16
The law and the prophets were until John: since that time the kingdom
of God is preached, and every man presseth into it.
17
And it is easier for heaven and earth to pass, than one tittle of the
law to fail.
Matthew
5:17
Think not that I am come to destroy the law, or the prophets: I am
not come to destroy, but to fulfil.
So,
regardless the obscurity about what exactly he's going to change, it
is apparent that he acknowledges the law as originating in the
biblical
god.
Objection
2.1.10) The biblical god is justified because he's warning his people
not to do evil.
Reply:
He's
saying that a woman who had premarital sex and then married someone
who did not know deserves
to be stoned to death,
and is commanding that they actually stone her to death.
That
cannot be excused as "warning his people not to do evil":
he's making false moral claims and issuing immoral commands.
Objection
2.1.11) You're just making an emotional appeal. You have no basis for
claiming that the actions of the biblical god are immoral, or that
the claims he made are false.
Reply:
Actually,
I'm appealing to people's sense of right and wrong, which is what
moral arguments are based on, ultimately.
In
fact, even many Christians agree with the moral assessment I'm making
- namely, that the command is appalling, and that the implication
that they deserve that punishment is not true -, which is why they
claim that the passages are not inspired.
As
I explained above, that objection fails
as well,
but
they do raise it because they agree that a being that behaves in the
way the biblical
god's
behavior is described in this case, would not be morally good.
That
aside, it's true that someone might insist that their moral sense is
in fact different, and that it tells them that stoning a woman to
death for having premarital sex and then marrying someone who didn't
know that, was morally acceptable in ancient Israel, and that she
deserved to be stoned to death. Those people won't be persuaded by
this example, and probably not by this full moral case, either.
However,
that does not mean that somehow my argument can be dismissed as an
"emotional appeal" because it appeals to the readers' sense
of right and wrong.
Furthermore,
with that criterion, someone might dismiss any
moral
case as an "emotional appeal", since ultimately all of them
do appeal to the reader's sense of right and wrong, even if
implicitly.
Objection
2.1.12) If stoning a woman to death for having sex before marriage
and then marrying someone who does not know were so clearly immoral
in the social context of the ancient Hebrews, the ancient Hebrews
would have realized that. However, they actually embraced the law,
because they saw it was good. It's your sense of right and wrong that
is giving you the wrong result, maybe because you're not considering
the social context, or for some other reason.
Reply:
This
kind of objection could be raised pretty much against any
moral
argument when the person making the assessment is not in the social
context in which the events take place, and the people in the given
context disagree. The ancient Hebrews are no exception in that
regard.
It's
not generally a good objection, and it fails in this case too.
But
let's consider a few cases to see why:
It
is clear to
a human being who is contemplating the matter carefully and
rationally that,
say, people who stop believing that Islam is true do not deserve to
be decapitated for that.
It
appears that it's not at all apparent to many people in places such
as Saudi Arabia, including those making the laws.
So,
many, perhaps most living in that context fail to see it.
Perhaps,
that's because some beliefs to which they have strong emotional
attachments get in the way, and/or they haven't even considered the
matter - it depends on the person -, but it is clear that people who
leave Islam do not deserve to be killed for that even
in the social contexts in which they're killed for that - and
we don't need to be part of that context to make that assessment.
It
is clear
to
a human being who is contemplating the matter carefully and
rationally that,
say, a woman who has sex before getting married, or who refuses to
marry a person chosen by her father, does not deserve to be killed
for that, or to have her face disfigured with acid for that, even
if the acid attack happens in a social context in which such acid
attacks are common, and even if they are believed to be morally right
by most of the people living in those social groups.
However,
many people around the world fail to realize that.
It
is clear that a human woman who has sex before marriage - today or
in ancient Israel, or in any other society -
does not deserve to be stoned
to death for that.
Well,
it's clear to
a human being who is contemplating the matter carefully and
rationally.
It
was not clear to ancient Hebrew lawmakers, and perhaps
to
most of the ancient Hebrews, and also to many other people in the
past, in different societies.
Generally,
people who live in brutal social environments usually do not dedicate
time to ponder whether their laws are just, and when they do, they
usually do so looking to the tainted lens of false beliefs that
they're emotionally attached to, and/or otherwise irrationally.
There
are of course, exceptions, which contributes to moral progress.
Also,
progress in living conditions results in more people assessing these
matters rationally, and not make up or approve of laws that are as
immoral as the ones under consideration. That also contributes to
moral progress.
Now,
let's assess the claim:
P:
An ancient Hebrew woman who had sex before marriage and then married
someone who did not know that she was not a virgin, deserved to be
stoned to death.
It
should be obvious that the claim is not true, and that stoning her
was immoral.
Readers
of course can use their own sense of right and wrong to make an
assessment.
That
is rational.
What
would not
be
rational would be to say - for instance - "but God
claimed
or implied that she deserved it, and God
is
morally perfect and not a liar, so the claim was true, and it was not
immoral to stone her."
That
would amount to essentially refuse to assess the claim by one's moral
sense, and instead conclude that she deserved to be stoned to death
and that stoning her was not immoral because of a baseless assumption
that God
made
the claim that she deserved it and/or commanded that she be stoned.
There
is no problem assuming for the sake of the argument that the biblical
god
claimed
or implied that she deserved to be stoned to death, and commanded
that she be stoned to death.
However,
when assessing the moral character of the biblical
god,
it would not be rational to assume that the biblical
god is
actually God.
That would not be an assessment at all, but simply a baseless
assumption of moral perfection.
The
same goes for other commands and claims I will address in later
subsections, including some probably even worse than this one - some
that involve burning
people
to death.
So,
I'm making a moral case in the sense people usually make moral
arguments - at least, when they're being rational about it.
If
a reader's moral sense truly tells her that a woman who lived in
ancient Israel and who had sex before marriage and then married
someone who did not know deserved to be stoned to death, then guess I
will not persuade that person - at least, not with this particular
example.
As
before, I would only ask readers to please use their own sense of
right and wrong to assess the matter, rather than, say, assume that
the biblical
god is
morally good, or that Jesus is, and that Jesus approved, etc.
2.2.)
Women and men burned to death for getting into an outlawed kind of
marriage
Leviticus
20:14
And if a man take a wife and her mother, it is wickedness: they shall
be burnt with fire, both he and they; that there be no wickedness
among you.
So,
it seems that if a man marries a woman and her mother, the biblical
god
commands
the three of them be burned
to death
-
a form of torture to death at least as bad as stoning, and probably
even worse.
Moreover,
he justifies this by claiming that those people are wicked, and that
in that way, wickedness is removed from among the ancient Hebrews.
What
he does not point out that burning
people to death for
entering a type of illegal marriage is indeed wicked, whereas
entering that kind of marriage does not appear to be so - but even if
there were something wrong with entering that kind of marriage, it
surely does not compare with burning
people do death for
doing so.
As
for objections, they're essentially the same as in the previous
subsection,
and are handled in the same manner.
2.3)
Women burned to death for prostitution
Leviticus
21:9
And the daughter of any priest, if she profane herself by playing the
whore, she profaneth her father: she shall be burnt with fire.
Once
again,
the
biblical
god
gives
the appalling command to burn
a woman to death for
being a
prostitute,
if her father happens to be a priest.
There
is also an implicit claim that she deserves it because she "profaneth
her father".
No
further comment is needed here; it should be obvious at this point
that the biblical
god
is
a monster. [5]
Objections
are handled as
before.
2.4)
Men executed for having sex with other men
Leviticus
20:13
If a man also lie with mankind, as he lieth with a woman, both of
them have committed an abomination: they shall surely be put to
death; their blood shall be upon them.
In
this particular case, the method of execution is not specified.
However,
execution itself would
be bad enough;
moreover, while the method is not specified, if the biblical
god did
not want men who have sex with men to be tortured to death but "just"
executed, then it was his responsibility to say so.
That's
because the methods of execution usually in place were forms of
torture to death, and that includes the methods he commanded in other
cases - such as stoning
people to death,
and burning
people to death.
Moreover,
given that he did not object to the use of the same brutal methods in
this case as well - despite his usual interventions giving laws and
the like - it seems reasonable to conclude that he at the very least
approve of such methods.
Most
of the objections are the same as before, and so they're similarly
handled,
but there are a few other objections to be briefly considered.
Objection
2.4.1) The punishment was death, not necessarily by stoning or any
other painful method.
Reply:
First,
as I just explained, that would be bad enough; moreover, it seems
that the biblical god at least approved of a particularly painful
method in this case too.
Second,
the biblical god not "only" commands that they be put to
death, but he implies that they deserve
it,
which is not true.
Objection
2.4.2) That command was only for cases of rape, not for all cases of
homosexual sex between men.
Reply:
The
command is that they both
be
killed.
Objection
2.4.3) That command was only for cases of male prostitution, or maybe
for some cases of ritualistic homosexual intercourse, not for all
cases of homosexual sex between men.
Reply:
Regardless,
they still didn't deserve to be put to death by any means, nor to be
tortured to death by the means used by the ancient Hebrews.
Objection
2.4.4) The command is justified to prevent the spread of sexually
transmitted illnesses.
Reply:
A
command by the creator of all sexually transmitted illnesses to
execute men for having sex with other men in order to prevent the
spread of such illnesses appears to be clearly unjust.
The
biblical god could have just stopped the illnesses all by himself -
or merely refrain from causing them.
That
aside, there was no claim that it was to prevent STDs that the
killing was carried out.
Rather,
the biblical
god claimed
that they deserved it, which is not true, and without saying a word
about STDs.
Even
leaving all of that aside, killing people to reduce the risk of
transmission of any of the STDs that afflicted the ancient Hebrews is
still
immoral.
2.5)
Women and non-human animals executed for having inter-species sex
Leviticus
20:16
And if a woman approach unto any beast, and lie down thereto, thou
shalt kill the woman, and the beast: they shall surely be put to
death; their blood shall be upon them.
In
addition to the usual unjust commands and false moral claims, in this
particular case the biblical god accuses any non-human animal for the
"crime" of having sex with a woman, claiming that their
blood "shall be upon them".
It's
not that the woman deserves to be killed, of course - objections are
handled as in previous cases, mutatis
mutandi,
so I will not repeated them for the sake of brevity -, or that this
case is any worse than the others.
However,
I mention this case because curiously, the biblical god is accusing
an entity that is not even a moral
agent[7] of
acting immorally.
Objection
2.5.1) The non-human animals were possessed by demons, who deserved
the punishment for having sex with women. [8]
Reply:
First,
that is not what the Bible says.
If
the biblical
god
meant
to say that this command only applied to possessed non-human animals,
he should have said so in order to be understood.
Instead,
the command - and the moral claim "their blood shall be upon
them" - applies to any woman, and any non-human animal she may
choose to have sex with - and she doesn't have to pick one that is
possessed.
Second,
this command is actually in line with a tendency to fail to realize
that some beings aren't moral beings, and punish them; I will provide
another example in the next
subsection.
Third,
if he wanted to kill demons possessing non-human animals, the
biblical
god
could
simply do it himself, leaving the non-human animal alone;
furthermore, there is no suggestion that a demon can be killed by the
ancient Hebrews and their methods for killing non-human animals.
Fourth,
a woman does not deserve to be put to death for having sex with a
non-human animal, so the command would still be immoral, and the
claim false.
2.6)
Oxen stoned to death as a punishment
Exodus
21:28
If an ox gore a man or a woman, that they die: then the ox shall be
surely stoned, and his flesh shall not be eaten; but the owner of the
ox shall be quit.
Exodus
21:32
If the ox shall push a manservant or a maidservant; he shall give
unto their master thirty shekels of silver, and the ox shall be
stoned.
While
killing a dangerous animal is acceptable, those
are clearly not just commands to kill a dangerous ox.
Rather,
the ox is punished
for his actions by being tortured to death by stoning.
In
brief:
a)
Killing the ox because he's dangerous would probably have been
acceptable in context.
b)
Killing the ox by stoning him to death because he was dangerous would
have been unacceptable. There were clearly more humane ways of
killing the ox, which were not more costly.
c)
Killing the ox by stoning him to death because of a belief that he
deserved to be stoned to death as a punishment was an unacceptable
behavior resulting from a serious moral confusion.
Yet,
commanding that the ox be put to death by stoning was a way of
implicitly saying that the ox deserved
it.
But he did not deserve it: the ox was just an ox.
So,
in addition to cruelty against non-human animals, here the biblical
god
is
implying that oxen who behaved in that manner were acting evilly, and
deserved to be tortured to death for their actions.
So,
he was implicitly making a false moral statement.
Objection
2.6.1) The oxen were possessed by demons, who deserved the punishment
for attacking humans. [8]
Reply:
That
is not what the Bible says, or how it was interpreted.
If
the biblical
god
meant
to say that this command only applied to possessed oxen, he should
have said so in order to be understood.
But
he did not, so the command applied to any ox, and even in the story,
there is no good reason to believe that any ox that gores a human was
possessed.
Objection
2.6.2) There was no implication that the ox deserved it. Stoning the
ox to death was simply the procedure for killing him. Before animal
rights activists brought confusion, there was no moral outrage at
killing an animal.
Reply:
First,
stoning was used as a method of punishment in ancient Israel. It was
not a normal procedure for killing oxen. So, there was an implicit
moral condemnation of the ox for his actions.
Second,
it's true that there was no moral outrage at killing an ox, and often
there is no such outrage today.
However,
those ancient Hebrews were morally outraged because
of the actions of the ox, which they believed was morally responsible
and which they stoned to death as a punishment.
That's deeply confused, and the
biblical
god was
deeply confused too - or deceiving those ancient Hebrews.
Third,
one does not need to be an animal rights activist to recognize that
killing an ox by stoning him to death when there are faster, less
painful and no more costly methods, is unacceptable because it's
unnecessarily cruel.
Still,
even assuming that unnecessary cruelty towards oxen is not immoral -
or was not immoral in the context of ancient Israel -, the fact
remains that the oxen in question did not deserve
to
be stoned to death.
2.7)
An assortment of more immoral commands and false moral claims
Just
to add some more evidence, I will quote a number of other immoral
commands issued and/or false moral claims made by the biblical god.
Num
15
32
And while the children of Israel were in the wilderness, they found a
man that gathered sticks upon the sabbath day.
33
And they that found him gathering sticks brought him unto Moses and
Aaron, and unto all the congregation.
34
And they put him in ward, because it was not declared what should be
done to him.
35
And the LORD said unto Moses, The man shall be surely put to death:
all the congregation shall stone him with stones without the camp.
36
And all the congregation brought him without the camp, and stoned him
with stones, and he died.
Leviticus
20:27 A man also or woman that hath a familiar spirit, or
that is a wizard, shall surely be put to death: they shall stone them
with stones: their blood shall be upon them.
Leviticus
24:16
And he that blasphemeth the name of the LORD, he shall surely be put
to death, and all the congregation shall certainly stone him: as well
the stranger, as he that is born in the land, when he blasphemeth the
name of the Lord, shall be put to death.
Deuteronomy
22:23-24
If a damsel that is a virgin be betrothed unto an husband, and a man
find her in the city, and lie with her.
Then
ye shall bring them both out unto the gate of that city, and ye shall
stone them with stones that they die; the damsel, because she cried
not, being in the city; and the man, because he hath humbled his
neighbour's wife: so thou shalt put away evil from among you.
Deuteronomy
25:11-12 When men strive together one with another, and the
wife of the one draweth near for to deliver her husband out of the
hand of him that smiteth him, and putteth forth her hand, and taketh
him by the secrets
Then
thou shalt cut off her hand, thine eye shall not pity her.
For
the sake of brevity, I will not add more commands and claims, but
many other examples of evil commands and false moral claims can
easily be found in the Bible.
So,
in brief, the biblical god made or implied a number of false moral
claims; for example, he claimed or implied that, in ancient Israel:
a)
If a man marries two women, and they're mother and daughter, then the
three of them deserve to be burned to death.
b)
If a woman has premarital sex, she deserves to be stoned to death -
at least, if she then marries someone who does not know it.
c)
If a woman is the daughter of a priest and she is also a prostitute,
she deserves to be burned to death.
d)
If a woman is betrothed to a man, but has sex with another man, then
she and her lover deserve to be stoned to death.
e)
If a woman has sex with a non-human animal, both the woman and the
non-human animal deserve to be killed.
In
addition to those claims or implications, the biblical
god gave the corresponding commands.
In
other words, he commanded the ancient Hebrews to stone to death, burn
to death, kill, etc., all the people and non-human animals in
question.
Objection
2.7.1) You're taking things out of context. You should consider
Jesus' life, and see that he was morally good. Then, if some passages
in the Old Testament appear problematic, you should realize that the
biblical god knows better than you do, and that once we've
established - based on Jesus' life, and/or other actions of the
biblical god described in the Old Testament -, that he is morally
good, we can conclude that the biblical god had good reasons for
giving those commands.
Reply:
That
would be an irrational way of assessing the moral character of the
biblical god:
essentially, that would amount to arbitrarily picking some of the
actions described in the Bible, "conclude" from them that a
being is morally good, and then claim that he must have had
mysterious reasons for the others.
However,
just as we can use our sense of right and wrong to assess that some
of his actions were not immoral, we can use it to assess that some of
his actions were profoundly evil.
Also,
it's important to point out that it's not the case that we don't have
sufficient information to make an assessment in the cases of the Old
Testament under consideration: assuming the description in the
biblical story - as usual -, we have the commands the biblical
god gave,
and the reasons he used by him to attempt to justify them, including
moral claims that are false, and we can ascertain that they're false
by means of using our own sense of right and wrong, and assessing
potential reasons and objections, as I've been doing so far - which
is precisely the same way in which we can assess that some
of
Jesus' actions are morally good.
The
good actions, however, do not make him not evil, just as a dictator
who tortures political opponents to death just for speaking out
against some of his policies is morally bad, even if he is kind to
his children, and even if he is good towards millions of people in
the country he rules over.
Objection
2.7.2) In the case of the biblical god, the interpretation that he is
evil even though sometimes he (and/or
his son) did the right thing, does not make sense, since it
would make no sense for a person to be so good sometimes and so bad
some other times. No person would act like that, unless he's insane,
and he does not appear to be so.
Reply:
First,
leaving aside the biblical story for a moment, the people who wrote
the passages of the Old Testament under consideration had very
different moral beliefs and agendas from those writing the New
Testament; further, different writers of the Old Testament had very
different beliefs and agendas, and the same goes for different
writers of the New Testament.
So,
any unusual feature in the character in the biblical god would be
unsurprising given the
real, historical context.
Still,
this is a moral case that does not require any assessments of
existence, so let's consider the matter assuming the events described
in the Bible:
Second,
actually, if
- but
it's a big "if" - any entity that does as much evil as I
claim the biblical god
does
in the events described in the Old Testament, and also does the
amount of good that biblical god
does
in both the New and the Old Testament (how much good he does is very
debatable, though), is insane, then the proper conclusion would not
be that the biblical god does
no evil, since the points I made earlier showing that he does evil
are unaffected by that consideration.
Rather,
the proper conclusion would be that the biblical
god is
indeed insane, even if, at some times, his mind goes back to some
kind of normalcy, or even if that normalcy is the most common
situations, and he only loses his mind in specific episodes.
Third,
even if it's true that a human who
behaves in such a manner is insane, it's not clear that we can extend
that assessment of mental illness to all other intelligent species,
or to all non-human intelligent entities with minds very different
from human minds and who don't belong to any species.
So,
I do not know that an assessment that the biblical
god is
insane would be warranted. On the other hand, an assessment that he's
evil is, for the reasons I've been explaining.
Fourth, in the case of humans, there are plenty
of people, in the past and today, who do both a lot of evil and a
good number of good deeds, often try to do what's right, and usually
believe themselves to be morally good, or mostly so.
For instance, many law-enforcement agents,
judges, and rulers in all kinds of oppressive regimes, and/or brutal
political and social environments, often justly arrest and/or punish
murderers, terrorists, rapists, bank robbers, thieves in general, con
artists, etc.
Sometimes they impose reasonable penalties -
not always, of course, but it's not difficult to find examples of
crimes in which the penalties are reasonable.
Some other times they impose immorally severe
penalties, or immorally punish people who shouldn't be punished at
all, like peaceful political opponents whose only "crime"
was to speak out, apostates, or people who have same-gender sex.
The amount of evil that people in the previous
category do or did is widely variable - both among cultures and
individuals -, and examples abound, both from the present (e.g.,
Cuba, China, Iran, Saudi Arabia), and the past (e.g., the Soviet
Union, the Aztecs, the Roman Empire, Mao's China, Europe in the
Middle Ages, and - of course - the ancient Hebrews).
Moreover, that kind of punishments - both the
good and the bad - were often supported by most of the population.
It's not clear at all that all of those people
were or are insane - it's not even plausible to think they were.
Even if we restrict ourselves to cases of
religiously driven brutality, like the ancient Hebrews, or the
Aztecs, it's rather implausible to think they were all or mostly
insane.
However,
if they are/were, that would only mean that insanity is a very common
feature of humans, but it makes no impact on the moral assessment of
the actions of the biblical
god.
Fifth
- and as a side comment - in many cases, the people described above
believed
in some entities who happened to have some of their own flaws and
strengths, often considerably magnified.
In
particular, the ancient Hebrews believed in the biblical
god.
An
obvious interpretation is that the biblical
god and
his actions were just imagined by some of the ancient Hebrews, and
his character reflects both the good and the bad in the customs of
those people, perhaps exaggerating some features, which makes him
particularly evil.
Later,
some other people wrote about Jesus, and yet some other people put
together the stories and identified Jesus with the biblical
god,
perhaps making the character somewhat more alien.
Objection
2.7.3) The biblical god is justified because he's warning his people
not to do evil.
Reply:
He's
making many false moral claims, and giving many immoral commands. The
actions for which people were to be burned to death, stoned to death,
etc., are not actions for which they deserved anything like that.
Even
if we assume for the sake of the argument that all of the actions for
which people are being burned to death, stoned to death, etc., were
indeed immoral - an implausible assumption, but let's let that pass
-, the biblical
god would
have been "warning" them not to do those particular immoral
actions...by falsely claiming or implying that those involved in said
actions deserved to be stoned to death, burned to death, etc., for
those actions, and by commanding others to carry out far
more immoral
actions,
like torturing those people to death - people who obviously did not
deserve it.
Moreover,
the biblical
god even
falsely claimed or implied that even the non-human animals involved
in some of those actions deserved to be killed, stoned to death,
etc., and gave the command to impose those punishments to those
non-human animals. Who was he warning, then? Oxen? Rams, perhaps?
The
fact is that the code gave by the biblical
god to
the ancient Hebrews is full of evil commands, false moral claims and
outright absurdities.
Stepping
out of the story for a moment, that's not surprising, given that this
code was invented by an ancient group of humans who were considerably
ignorant, and sometimes extremely brutal.
But
assuming that these were the commands given by the biblical
god,
he was clearly evil.
And
assuming that they weren't, then Jesus was mistaken by believing they
were, and so Christianity is not true either way.
2.8) The hardness of the hearts of the
ancient Hebrews
Earlier
in this section,
when addressing the case of women who were stoned to death for having
premarital sex, I considered the "hard hearts" objection,
showing why the objection fails to excuse the biblical
god's
actions.
In this subsection, I will address it again in
greater detail:
The
basic idea is that Jesus' claim in the case of divorce also extends
to other dispositions of the law given by the biblical
god to
the ancient Hebrews:
Mark 10
2
And the Pharisees came to him, and asked him, Is it lawful for a man
to put away his wife? tempting him.
3 And he answered and said unto them, What did Moses command you?
4 And they said, Moses suffered to write a bill of divorcement, and to put her away.
5 And Jesus answered and said unto them, For the hardness of your heart he wrote you this precept.
6 But from the beginning of the creation God made them male and female.
7 For this cause shall a man leave his father and mother, and cleave to his wife;
8 And they twain shall be one flesh: so then they are no more twain, but one flesh.
9 What therefore God hath joined together, let not man put asunder.
So, according to this objection, the laws I addressed before were
given to the ancient Hebrews because of the hardness of their hearts,
but we should not conclude that the biblical
god actually believed that it was morally acceptable to, say,
burn a woman to death because she was the daughter of a priest and a
prostitute, or stoning her to death because she had premarital sex
and then married someone who did not know that.
This
objection, however, fails to excuse the actions of the biblical
god for - at least - the following reasons:
First,
the biblical god commanded the ancient
Hebrews to engage in those heinous acts of torture to death by
burning or stoning people to death - among other atrocities.
How
would the "hardness" of their hearts excuse giving them the
order to commit such atrocities.
Second,
the biblical god clearly implied that the
people to be burned, stoned, killed etc., and even the non-human
animals to be punished, deserved to be so punished.
That's
apparent given that he commanded all of that while claiming or
implying that he was good.
Alternatively,
one can easily see that he implied that they deserved to be punished
in that way by considering the specific wording of most of the
commands; for instance:
Deuteronomy
22: 21
Then they shall bring out the damsel to the door of her father's
house, and the men of her city shall stone her with stones that she
die: because she hath wrought folly in Israel, to play the whore in
her father's house: so shalt thou put evil away from among you.
Here,
he claim is that they shall stone her because she hath wrought
folly in Israel, implicitly saying that she deserves to be stoned
to death because of her actions.
Leviticus
20:27 A man also or woman that hath a familiar spirit, or
that is a wizard, shall surely be put to death: they shall stone them
with stones: their blood shall be upon them.
In
this case, the biblical god claims that their blood shall be upon
them, which
is a way of implying that they deserve to be punished in the
prescribed way.
Leviticus
21:9 And the daughter of any priest, if she profane herself by
playing the whore, she profaneth her father: she shall be burnt with
fire.
In this case, there is also an attempted justification for the command: "she profaneth her father" - and implicitly, that's why she allegedly deserves to burn with fire.
Leviticus
20:16
And if a woman approach unto any beast, and lie down thereto, thou
shalt kill the woman, and the beast: they shall surely be put to
death; their blood shall be upon them.
Once
again, here the claim is that "their blood shall be upon them",
implying that both the woman and the non-human animal that had sex
with her - regardless of species - deserved to be put to death.
Leviticus
20:13
If a man also lie with mankind, as he lieth with a woman, both of
them have committed an abomination: they shall surely be put to
death; their blood shall be upon them.
As
in previous cases, the biblical
god
claims is that their blood shall be upon them.
So,
it's clear that the biblical
god
did
claim or implied that they deserved to be punished in the prescribed
manner, and that it wasn't immoral to inflict that punishment on
them.
Third,
regardless of whether their hearts were hard or not, the biblical
god was
far more powerful, and was giving them a law, sometimes making
threats and taking direct action to coerce them into following it.
So,
he clearly could have made things much better if he had refrained
from issuing evil commands and from making false moral claims.
In
fact, by giving evil commands and making false moral claims, he was
reinforcing
their immoral practices and beliefs, and the "hardness" of
their hearts.[9]
Fourth,
Jesus himself believed that the law was good, going by the biblical
story:
Luke
16:
6
The law and the prophets were until John: since that time the kingdom
of God is preached, and every man presseth into it.
17
And it is easier for heaven and earth to pass, than one tittle of the
law to fail.
Matthew
5:17
Think not that I am come to destroy the law, or the prophets: I am
not come to destroy, but to fulfil.
Unless
Jesus was lying, it seems that when he claimed that, he believed that
following the law was not morally wrong.
3) David's murder of Uriah, and the biblical
god's immoral reaction
According
to the Bible, David had sex with Uriah's wife, Bathsheba, and
then had Uriah killed.
The
biblical god
punished David for that.
The
problem is how the
biblical
god punished
him:
2 Samuel 11:
1.
And it came to pass, after the year was expired, at the time when
kings go forth to battle, that David sent Joab, and his servants with
him, and all Israel; and they destroyed the children of Ammon, and
besieged Rabbah. But David tarried still at Jerusalem.
2.
And it came to pass in an eveningtide, that David arose from off his
bed, and walked upon the roof of the king's house: and from the roof
he saw a woman washing herself; and the woman was very beautiful to
look upon.
3.
And David sent and enquired after the woman. And one said, Is not
this Bathsheba, the daughter of Eliam, the wife of Uriah the Hittite?
4.And
David sent messengers, and took her; and she came in unto him, and he
lay with her; for she was purified from her uncleanness: and she
returned unto her house.
5.
And the woman conceived, and sent and told David, and said, I am with
child.
6.
And David sent to Joab, saying, Send me Uriah the Hittite. And Joab
sent Uriah to David.
7.
And when Uriah was come unto him, David demanded of him how Joab did,
and how the people did, and how the war prospered.
8.
And David said to Uriah, Go down to thy house, and wash thy feet. And
Uriah departed out of the king's house, and there followed him a mess
of meat from the king.
9.
But Uriah slept at the door of the king's house with all the servants
of his lord, and went not down to his house.
10.
And when they had told David, saying, Uriah went not down unto his
house, David said unto Uriah, Camest thou not from thy journey? why
then didst thou not go down unto thine house?
11.
And Uriah said unto David, The ark, and Israel, and Judah, abide in
tents; and my lord Joab, and the servants of my lord, are encamped in
the open fields; shall I then go into mine house, to eat and to
drink, and to lie with my wife? as thou livest, and as thy soul
liveth, I will not do this thing.
12.
And David said to Uriah, Tarry here to day also, and to morrow I will
let thee depart. So Uriah abode in Jerusalem that day, and the
morrow.
13.
And when David had called him, he did eat and drink before him; and
he made him drunk: and at even he went out to lie on his bed with the
servants of his lord, but went not down to his house.
14.
And it came to pass in the morning, that David wrote a letter to
Joab, and sent it by the hand of Uriah.
15.
And he wrote in the letter, saying, Set ye Uriah in the forefront of
the hottest battle, and retire ye from him, that he may be smitten,
and die.
16.
And it came to pass, when Joab observed the city, that he assigned
Uriah unto a place where he knew that valiant men were.
17.
And the men of the city went out, and fought with Joab: and there
fell some of the people of the servants of David; and Uriah the
Hittite died also.
...
26.
And when the wife of Uriah heard that Uriah her husband was dead, she
mourned for her husband.
27.
And when the mourning was past, David sent and fetched her to his
house, and she became his wife, and bare him a son. But the thing
that David had done displeased the LORD.
So, the biblical
god was displeased with David's treacherous and murderous
actions. Let's see how he punished David:
2
Samuel 11:
11.
Thus saith the LORD, Behold, I will raise up evil against thee out of
thine own house, and I will take thy wives before thine eyes, and
give them unto thy neighbour, and he shall lie with thy wives in the
sight of this sun.
12.
For thou didst it secretly: but I will do this thing before all
Israel, and before the sun.
So, David's wives -
completely non-guilty in this matter - are going to be "given"
to David's neighbor, to be raped if they don't feel like having sex
with him - their consent is not required.
But there is more:
2 Samuel 11:
14. Howbeit, because by this deed thou hast
given great occasion to the enemies of the LORD to blaspheme, the
child also that is born unto thee shall surely die.
15.
And Nathan departed unto his house. And the LORD struck the child
that Uriah's wife bare unto David, and it was very sick.
16.
David therefore besought God for the child; and David fasted, and
went in, and lay all night upon the earth.
17.
And the elders of his house arose, and went to him, to raise him up
from the earth: but he would not, neither did he eat bread with them.
18.
And it came to pass on the seventh day, that the child died...
So,
the biblical
god decided
to target someone else: David and Bathsheba's son was slowly killed
by the biblical
god,
who caused him to be very sick for a week, and then die.
The
biblical
god's
actions speak for themselves, so no further comment is needed.
Objection
3.1) The
biblical god has sovereignty over life and death. He gives life, and
he has the right to take it. He does no wrong by killing David and
Bathsheba's son.
Reply:
First,
there is no good reason to believe that he has the right to take
someone's life just because he created that person.
Second,
in any event, the biblical
god is
not "only" killing the child. He's making him very sick,
with an illness that kills him in a
week.
Someone
might suggest that, perhaps, the child was always unconscious and
suffered no pain, but there is no good reason to assume so.
Third,
even if we leave the child aside, that would not excuse the biblical
god's
decision to have David's wives raped by David's neighbor.
Objection
3.2) That passage was an allegory. Those events never happened. The
biblical god was teaching the ancient Hebrews a moral lesson against
adultery and murder.
Reply:
Then,
the biblical
god inspired
a story making David look like a murderer, and making himself look
like a rapist, a torturer and a murderer, and when the story wasn't
interpreted allegorically, the biblical
god didn't
object to that, further confusing the ancient Hebrews who read those
stories.
Objection
3.3) David's actions are a historical account. Only the actions of
the biblical
god are
allegorical.
Reply:
That
appears to be picking and choosing.
But
leaving that aside, the fact would still be that the biblical
god
inspired
a story making himself look like a rapist, a torturer and a murderer,
and when the story wasn't interpreted allegorically, the biblical
god
didn't
object to that, further confusing the ancient Hebrews who read those
stories.
Objection 3.4) Those passages are not
inspired. They're not scriptural. They should be removed from the
Bible.
Reply:
If
so, then why
didn't
Jesus say so?
Why
did he not correct that error?
Why
did he not remove those passages portraying his father as a monster?
In
fact, given that Jesus believed that the
law of the Old Testament
came
from the biblical
god,
then clearly he did not oppose to the atrocities in that law.
The
fact that Jesus also did not claim this passage to be non-inspired
seems to be in line with Jesus' beliefs and behavior, which reflects
both belief in the inspiration of the Hebrew Bible, and approval of
the actions of the biblical
god
portrayed
in it.
4)
Jesus and the biblical god
Even
though I've dealt with this matter to some extent earlier, in this
section I will address in more detail the Gospels' account of the
relation between Jesus' and the biblical
god.
This
wouldn't be required under the assumption - which is a belief held by
versions of Christianity comprising nearly all adherents - that Jesus
is the same entity as the biblical
god,
and that the Old Testament is inspired.
However,
in order to cover alternative versions of Christianity who focus only
on Jesus - who they claim is morally perfect - and the Gospels, let's
see what the Gospels say about these matters:
Luke
16:
6
The law and the prophets were until John: since that time the kingdom
of God is preached, and every man presseth into it.
17
And it is easier for heaven and earth to pass, than one tittle of the
law to fail.
Matthew
5:17
Think not that I am come to destroy the law, or the prophets: I am
not come to destroy, but to fulfil.
So,
while it's not entirely clear what it is that will change, in those
passages Jesus implies that the biblical
god
exists,
and
also
implicitly endorses
the
biblical
god's
actions from a moral perspective.
But
there are even more obvious passages, in which Jesus claims or
implies that the biblical
god
is
morally good - which is a false moral claim, given what we've seen in
previous
sections:
Mat
19:16
And, behold, one came and said unto him, Good Master, what good thing
shall I do, that I may have eternal life?
Mat
19:17 And he said unto him, Why callest thou me good? there is
none good but one, that is, God: but if thou wilt enter into life,
keep the commandments.
There
is no question here that Jesus' claims that
the
biblical
god
is
morally good, and in fact, Jesus endorses the Old Testament as
inspired.
Let's
take a look at the transfiguration of Jesus:
Mark
9
2
And after six days Jesus taketh with him Peter, and James, and John,
and leadeth them up into an high mountain apart by themselves: and he
was transfigured before them.
3 And his raiment became shining, exceeding
white as snow; so as no fuller on earth can white them.
4 And there appeared unto them Elias with
Moses: and they were talking with Jesus.
5 And Peter answered and said to Jesus, Master,
it is good for us to be here: and let us make three tabernacles; one
for thee, and one for Moses, and one for Elias.
6 For he wist not what to say; for they were
sore afraid.
7 And there was a cloud that overshadowed them:
and a voice came out of the cloud, saying, This is my beloved Son:
hear him.
8 And suddenly, when they had looked round
about, they saw no man any more, save Jesus only with themselves.
Once
again, the connection is made apparent in this passage:
Jesus
is talking to Moses, but it's obvious that Jesus is not rebuking
Moses for the evil commands he issued and false moral claims he made,
or saying that those claims and commands did not come from the
biblical god.
Rather,
this passage actually stresses the links.
In
context, the voice coming from the cloud is unmistakably that of the
biblical god, and Jesus neither rebukes
him for the atrocities he committed, nor claims that Moses committed
those atrocities on his own.
In
brief, there is no question here that the biblical
god, Jesus, Elias and Moses are all on the same page so to speak,
and in particular, Jesus endorses the actions of the biblical
god described in the Old Testament, and those of Moses following
the biblical god's commands.
Since
many of those commands were profoundly immoral,
and the moral claims false, it's clear that Jesus wasn't morally
perfect.
Moreover,
he was - according to the story, as usual - either the same entity as
the biblical god, or someone working for
him, or with him.
Objection
4.1) The passage of the transfiguration is allegorical. It didn't
really happen, and the Gospel does not claim it happened.
Reply:
It's
irrelevant to the
matter
at hand whether it's allegorical or not: even if it's allegorical,
what is clear in that passage is that, according to the Gospel:
a)
Jesus and the biblical
god
are
at least on the same side.
b)
Jesus endorsed the actions of the biblical
god,
described in the Old Testament, and claimed that the biblical
god
was
morally good.
c)
Jesus endorsed the actions of Moses, described in the Old Testament,
as long as Moses was following commands by the biblical
god
So,
whether a correct interpretation of that particular passage is an
allegorical one is beside the point.
Moreover,
even if we leave that passage aside - but there is no good reason to
do so -, the other passages I quoted are enough to show that Jesus
endorsed the actions of the biblical
god
described
in the Old Testament, and claimed that the biblical
god
was
morally good.
Objection
4.2) Jesus was a reformist. He didn't come to endorse the Mosaic Law,
but to change it. He even said that the law was given to the ancient
Hebrews because their hearts were hard.
Reply:
It is true that, on one occasion, Jesus said that a specific part of the law had been given because of the hardness of the hearts of the ancient Hebrews.
However, even if Jesus had said or implied that that was the case of all of the commands I considered earlier - which he did not -, that would still fail to provide any excuse for the actions of the biblical god, as I explained in a previous section.
Jesus did not say that the Old Testament was not inspired and that the actions described in it weren't actually the actions of the biblical god, but instead claimed or implied that those were in fact the actions of the biblical god.
So, even if Jesus was a reformist, he still believed that the actions of the biblical god were not immoral - a false moral belief -, and that the biblical god was morally good - yet another false moral belief, given the biblical god's numerous atrocities -, and in fact Jesus claimed that the biblical god was morally good - a false moral claim.
In short, Jesus had false moral beliefs, and made false moral claims, endorsing the actions of a monster.
If he was the same entity as the biblical god, then Jesus himself was a monster.
If not, he was at least confused about the moral character of the biblical god, if not just lying about that.
Objection 4.3) You're taking those passages out of context by focusing on the connection between Jesus and the Old Testament, instead of taking into consideration all the good Jesus did, as described in the Gospels.
Reply:
I'm not taking anything out of context. Rather, I'm considering the context and making the connection between Jesus and the biblical god.
Objecting
that I'm only focusing on the bad is out of place: it would be like
saying that if I said that a dictator who tortured people to death
just for peacefully expressing disagreement with some of his policies
acted immorally, I would be taking things out of context because the
dictator in question, say, loved his children, and I did not point
that out.
In
fact, even if the dictator who tortured people to death just for
disagreeing with some of his policies loved his children, and even if
he did morally good things in a number of occasions - even in many
occasions, actually -, that would not change the fact that he acted
in a very immoral manner when he tortured people to death just for
peacefully expressing disagreement.
The
same goes for someone who is the dictator's enforcer, or a supporter:
their degree of culpability would have to be assessed on a case by
case manner, but surely there is some culpability on their part.
In
the case of Jesus, if he is in fact the same entity as the biblical
god,
then even if he did good on some or many occasions, the fact remains
that he's profoundly evil, given the previous
sections.
If
he is not the same entity as the biblical
god,
then Christianity in most of its versions is not true. Moreover, if
he's not the same entity as the biblical
god,
but believed that the biblical
god was
morally good - as the Gospels show -, he still have false moral
beliefs,
and he made false moral claims when he expressed those beliefs.
Objection 4.4) Given all the good that Jesus did, and given that he's the same being as the biblical god, we can tell that the biblical god must have had some reasons for the commands he gave, for the false moral claims, and for other actions, even if we don't know what reason that is.
Reply:
First, that would be an irrational way of assessment of the evidence.
We have to take a look at all of the description, concluding that if Jesus was the same being as the biblical god, he was profoundly evil, even if he also did good things a number of times.
Second, given the extent of the atrocities committed by the biblical god and by his servant Moses, the claim of "mysterious reasons" appears even more obviously unreasonable - if possible.
For that matter, someone could claim that Pol Pot wasn't morally bad, but was acting under the orders of a morally good creator who had mysterious reasons.
Objection 4.5) The passages of the Old Testament that you quoted earlier are not inspired, and are actually false: the biblical god did not command or do any of that. Any passages of the Gospels that say or suggest otherwise are also neither inspired nor true.
Reply:
First, the connections to the Old Testament in general and to the laws given to the ancient Hebrews in particular are an integral part of the story in the Gospels. Removing them would make much of the story even more absurd.
Second, and leaving that aside, it's unreasonable to pick and choose like that. Why remove those particular passages?
5)
Jesus and "family values"
Acting
very much like a cult leader, Jesus told his disciples:
Luke
14:
26
If any man come to me, and hate not his father, and mother, and wife,
and children, and brethren, and sisters, yea, and his own life also,
he cannot be my disciple.
27 And whosoever doth not bear his cross, and
come after me, cannot be my disciple.
28 For which of you, intending to build a
tower, sitteth not down first, and counteth the cost, whether he have
sufficient to finish it?
29 Lest haply, after he hath laid the
foundation, and is not able to finish it, all that behold it begin to
mock him,
30 Saying, This man began to build, and was not
able to finish.
31 Or what king, going to make war against
another king, sitteth not down first, and consulteth whether he be
able with ten thousand to meet him that cometh against him with
twenty thousand?
32 Or else, while the other is yet a great way
off, he sendeth an ambassage, and desireth conditions of peace.
33 So likewise, whosoever he be of you that
forsaketh not all that he hath, he cannot be my disciple.
So, Jesus was telling them to abandon and hate their families: their
parents, children, siblings, and so on. He even told them to hate
themselves - but not to hate him, of course.
Now,
if Jesus was in fact the biblical god,
this immoral action pales in comparison with the previously
described
atrocities,
so it's just a drop in the ocean.
If
the biblical god
existed
and Jesus was a servant of that entity, what he did in this
particular case was immoral, and we can add that to the general
immorality of his actions in the service of the biblical
god.
But if Jesus was a fully human preacher - which is actually the case
-, this action indicates that he was far from being a good role
model.
Rather, he was a cult leader, spreading his false religion and
telling people to hate and abandon their families.
Objection 5.1) It would have been immoral for a fully human preacher to say that, but Jesus is the same being as the biblical god, and as the creator, he has sovereignty.
Reply:
First, if he's the same being as the biblical god, then the previous sections show that he's very evil.
Second, that aside, there is no good reason to think that being the creator would excuse him for asking them to hate and abandon their families.
Objection 5.2) That's a bad translation or interpretation. Jesus did not mean to say that they had to hate their families, but only that they should take second place to their dedication to Jesus.
Reply:
Even if that were the case, the point remains:
If Jesus was the same being as the biblical god, then the previous sections show that he's very evil.
If he was a servant of the biblical god, that may be less bad, but still so.
If he was a fully human preacher with no connection to the biblical god, this action shows that he was a cult leader telling people to abandon their families and put him first, while he was spreading his false religion.
Objection 5.3) That passages is false. Jesus did not say that.
Reply:
First, picking and choosing which passages are true and which ones are not is an unreasonable way of assessing the evidence.
So, whoever raises that objection but still claims that the Gospels are generally reliable, have the burden of arguing their case.
Second, even if this passages is false, other passages still make a successful moral case, so the person raising that objection would have to reject many passages of both testaments, and at the same time provide a good argument to show that those particular passages - but not their favored ones - ought to be rejected.
That would be a very heavy burden on any claimant; moreover, it would be incompatible with nearly all versions of Christianity.
6)
Hell
In
earlier sections, I gave moral arguments that appear to suffice to
reject Christianity as untrue, based on some of the actions of the
biblical god
described
in the Old Testament.
However,
based on the New Testament - as usually interpreted -, one can
conclude that there are even worse actions carried out by the
biblical god: arguments from Hell also
show that Christianity is not true.
More
precisely, they show that versions of Christianity comprising the
vast majority of believers aren't true: In this section, I will
consider different alternatives, assessing the consequences for
Christianity.
6.1)
Infinite Hell vs. finite Hell or no Hell
Versions
of Christianity comprising the vast majority of adherents contend
that Hell is infinite. This includes the largest denomination by far
- the Roman Catholic Church -, which does not claim that Hell is a
place of fire, but does claim it's infinite. [10]
However,
some claim otherwise, or even deny that there is Hell at all.
In
what follows, I will only focus on those that hold that Hell is
infinite.
The
rest of the versions are not affected by the following arguments, but
are still vulnerable
to
the
previous
ones.
6.2)
Hell as a place of torment vs. Hell as some state of mind or state of
being
For
most of the history of Christianity, Hell has been seen by most as a
place of punishment, where the damned endure a number of torments.
However,
nowadays there are competing views, including those that call Hell "a
state of mind", or "a state of being".
Now,
according to Christianity, the dead will eventually resurrect, so
they will have bodies.
So,
they will have to be put somewhere, so if the damned will be
separated from the blessed - i.e., they won't be in the same place -,
then whether the torment is caused by fire or by some other
condition, it's difficult to see how that would not be a place of
torment.
In
any case, and while a lot could be said about those issues, it's not
important to the moral case I'm making: whether the word "Hell"
is used to denote the place where the damned will go, or some state
of mind or being of those people, the important point here is that
those people will endure eternal suffering, without possibility of
escape - they don't even have the choice to be annihilated to end
their torment.
Once
it's clear that such eternal torment is imposed by the biblical
god, the
immorality of his actions will
hopefully be apparent.
6.3)
Hell as
imposed
by the biblical god vs. Hell as chosen by the damned
While
the traditional view of Hell, for most of the history of
Christianity, seems to have been that it was a punishment imposed by
the biblical god, nowadays there are
Christians who claim that even though Hell is a form of infinite
suffering, it's freely chosen by the damned.
However,
that alternative view is clearly untenable: it is easy to show, that
if the biblical god
is
the creator and there is infinite Hell - in any of its variants -,
then infinite Hell is imposed by the biblical
god on
the damned, rather than chosen by them:
Barring
serious mental illness, people would not choose to suffer for
eternity - not even bad people would make such choice -, unless,
perhaps, they sacrifice themselves to save others, but that's not the
case of under consideration.
As
for those suffering from serious mental illness, they should not
qualified as competent to make their own choice and endure eternal
torment from
it.
For
instance, we do not allow mentally ill people to, say, set themselves
on fire because they want to suffer, and for good reasons - and
that's not even eternal suffering.
So,
given the above, it is apparent that Hell is not chosen by the
damned, but imposed on them by the biblical
god.
Moreover,
and while the previous considerations suffice, one can also point out
that the damned are not allowed to leave or choose to be annihilated
after a finite time in Hell, even though the biblical
god -
who created the rule according to which they end up in Hell - could
easily let them go or destroy them, if he accepted.
Objection
6.3.1) The people in Hell freely choose to suffer for eternity by
means of freely choosing to sin (or
rejecting the Gospel, or generally meeting the conditions to avoid
Hell in each version of Christianity),
like criminals put themselves in prison or death row by freely
choosing to commit crimes.
Reply:
Let's
consider the following scenario:
Alice
believes Hell does not exist.
Even if she was negligent and
that's why she believes Hell does not exist – that is not the
case, but leaving that aside - the fact remains that she believes
Hell does not exist.
So, when she fails to meet the conditions to
avoid Hell, she never expected that the consequences of her not
meeting such conditions would be to go to Hell.
For instance,
let's say Alice read the Gospel and was told by some Christians that
if she failed to believe, or generally to trust Jesus as her lord and
savior, she would go to Hell.
Some other Christians told her that there were some other conditions
she had to meet in order to avoid Hell. And then, some Muslims told
her there were some other conditions.
Now, Alice – very
reasonably, but leaving that aside – did not believe any of the
claims.
In fact, she came to the conclusion that the laws in
question – namely, laws imposed by an immensely powerful
creator that establish that failing to meet certain conditions would
result in her going to Hell forever – did not exist.
Then,
clearly she did not choose to be in Hell; that is the case regardless
of whether Hell is a state of mind/being, a place of torment by fire,
etc.; the point is that Alice
did not choose to suffer for eternity.
If
Alice indeed ends up in Hell, that's not her choice, but was put
there. So, if Alice suffers for eternity, that suffering is not her
choice, but the free choice of the biblical
god, who imposes that suffering on her.
Now, let's consider another scenario:
Bob never heard of Christianity, Islam, or Hell. Moreover, the
concept of eternal punishment is totally alien to him as well.
Once again, the conclusion is that he did not choose to suffer for
eternity.
So, if Bob does end up suffering for eternity in Hell, then:
a)
If Hell is a place, then the biblical god
tossed
Bob in there.
He may have done so personally or by proxy, or by some mechanism that
sends people who fail to meet certain criterion to Hell, but the
method of placing Bob in Hell is beside the point here.
b)
If Hell is not a place but a state of mind or state of being, then
the biblical god made
humans in a way such that, regardless of what they want, if they
don't meet certain criterion, they enter a state of perpetual
suffering, of which they cannot ever escape.
Moreover,
the biblical god has
no mercy on them: even if they ask to be annihilated instead, the
biblical god sticks
to the infinite suffering instead.
Whether
the biblical god
imposes
eternal suffering as a punishment or for some other reason, the point
here is that he does impose eternal suffering.
That
aside, even in the case of criminals, they generally do not
choose
to be put in prison or death row.
For instance, let's consider the following scenario:
In Iran, the law establishes that men who have sex with men shall be
put to death.
Also, in Iran, and not expecting to get caught, Ali has sex with
Mahmoud.
They get caught and put in prison for that, and later they're dragged
to the place where they'll be executed, while they beg for mercy.
Eventually, they are executed.
It's obviously not the case that they freely choose to be arrested or
executed, even if they freely chose to have sex with each other.
Granted, in the case of infinite suffering imposed by an
all-powerful, all-seeing entity, there is a difference: it would be
absurd to believe one has a shot at escaping that fate, if one
believes that such entity exists and has imposed such rules.
However, the point is that however one slices it, people do not
freely choose to be in Hell - regardless of what else they freely
choose to do.
Now, there are figurative senses in which someone can say
that, for instance, if Tom robs a bank, he “put himself in
prison”.
For instance, someone could say that Tom put himself in prison
meaning that Tom made a free choice for which he deserved to
be put in prison.
That may well be true, whereas it's not true that Ali and Mahmoud
made a free choice for which they deserved to be arrested or
executed. But in any case, this is a figurative sense of the
expression “chose to be put in prison”.
In a literal
sense, neither Ali or Mahmoud chose to be executed, nor did Tom
choose to be put in prison.
Back
to the cases of Alice and
Bob, it's even more clear - if possible - that
they did not literally made a free choice to suffer infinitely in
Hell, but that if they end up suffering infinitely, that suffering
was imposed on them by the biblical god.
Objection
6.3.2) The people in Hell freely choose to suffer for eternity,
knowing that they would suffer for eternity.
Reply:
They
would have to be severely mentally ill to do that, unless that's a
condition to save someone else from the same fate, which is not the
case under consideration.
Apart
from the fact that that would limit Hell in a way that no version of
Christianity holds (i.e., Hell only for some severely mentally ill
people), it would still be an unacceptable action on the part of the
biblical
god to
make a rule that some severely mentally ill people will suffer for
eternity if they, due to their mental illness, choose to do so.
Objection
6.3.3) The people in Hell freely choose to reject the biblical
god,
who is God,
and Hell is separation from the biblical god.
Even
if the damned do not know that human minds are such that being
separated from the biblical god results in terrible suffering - but
they should know -, their choice to be separated from him is a free
choice nonetheless. The biblical god is only respecting their free
choice.
Reply:
First,
previous sections show that the biblical
god is
not God
-
since he's not morally perfect -, but there is no need to rely on
previous sections.
The
point is that the claim that the biblical
god is
God
is
shown to be false by the fact that he inflicts infinite torment on
people in Hell.
Second,
it is not the case that they choose to reject the biblical
god.
In
many cases, people never even heard of him, and even when they have,
they assess
hat
he does not exist and/or that he's a monstrous imaginary character.
That
is an assessment, not a choice.
For
instance, I do not choose to believe that the biblical
god
does
not exist any more than I would choose to believe that, say, Athena,
Thor or Darth Vader does not exist.
The
same goes many if not all people who have heard of the biblical
god
and
do not believe that he exists.
Even
if there were any irrationality in making that assessment - there is
not, but that aside -, the fact would remain that we do not make such
a choice.
The
same applies to the assessment that he is a monstrous character.
That's an assessment, not a choice.
Third,
even
if, say,
Mary
freely
chose to be separated from the biblical
god
for
eternity without knowing that that would result in eternal torment,
and even if she is at epistemic fault for not knowing, that
still would not change the fact that the endless torment is imposed
by the biblical
god,
rather
than being freely chosen by Mary.
On
that note, let's consider the following scenario:
Let
us suppose that some human scientists genetically engineer some
intelligent beings based on, say, pigs, but vastly modified. They are
very intelligent, capable of talking, and they live for over a
millennium.
Also,
the scientists design their brains so that, if they're not in the
presence of humans, their minds enter a state of horrible suffering -
let's call that state "Bell".
Now,
let's say that Pig is one of those beings, and his makers give him
the chance of choosing to remain in their company, or to go to some
other place, in the presence of individuals of his species and some
other species, but no humans.
Additionally,
they give Pig some clues that, if he follows them properly, would
lead him to the conclusions that:
a)
In the absence of humans, he will be in a state of terrible
suffering.
b)
If he chooses to be in the presence of his makers, he will be in the
presence of humans for the rest of his life. But if he chooses
otherwise, he won't be in the presence of humans ever again.
c)
He will not be killed by request, and he won't be allowed to kill
himself, either: there will be robots that will stop him from killing
himself if he tried.
d)
He almost certainly still has many centuries to live.
Now,
Pig makes a badly mistaken assessment - let's say he's epistemically
guilty -, and fails to realize that he will suffer at all if he's not
in the presence of humans.
Then,
Pig chooses not to be in the presence of his makers anymore.
So,
his makers put him in a place without humans and - as he should have
expected but
didn't expect at all -,
Pig begins to suffer tremendously.
In
desperation, he asks to be put in the presence of humans again -
there are no humans before him, but there are cameras and microphones
that let his makers know what he's doing, saying, etc.
But
his makers refuse, telling him that he freely chose to be in Bell,
and they're only respecting his free choice.
So,
he asks his makers to have mercy on him and kill him. But his makers
reply that he's freely chosen to be in Bell for the rest of his life,
which will almost certainly last for several centuries.
It
is apparent in the scenario that Pig did not choose to be in Bell.
In
other words, he did not choose to be in a state of terrible
suffering.
It
is true that he chose not to be in the presence of his makers - or
other humans -, but that does not change the fact that Bell
is not chosen by Pig; it's imposed by his makers.
In
other words, the
suffering is
not chosen; it's imposed by his makers.
Given
the amount of suffering, it's clear that Pig's makers are torturing
him.
It
should be also obvious that the actions of Pig's makers are morally
unacceptable, but I will address the evil of hell in
the next subsection.
In
this
subsection,
the main point is that regardless of moral assessments, the fact is
that Hell, like Bell, is not chosen by the people in Hell, but
imposed on them.
In
other words, just as horrible suffering is not chosen by Pig but is
instead inflicted on him by his human makers, infinite torment is not
chosen by the people in Hell but is inflicted on them by the biblical
god,
regardless of whether Hell is a place, a state of mind, or whatever
it is.
Objection
6.3.3) Even if infinite suffering is inflicted on the damned by the
biblical god, rather than chosen by the damned, he is respecting
their free choice to be separated from him from eternity.
Even
if the damned do not know that human minds are such that being
separated from the biblical god results in terrible suffering - but
they should know -, their choice to be separated from him is a free
choice nonetheless. The biblical god is respecting their free choice.
Reply:
Actually,
the biblical god would still be inflicting infinitely suffering on
them, so this objection fails simply because it entails that Hell is
not a choice, but is instead imposed by the biblical
god:
in other words, the infinite
suffering is
inflicted by the biblical
god,
so Hell is inflicted and not chosen.
So,
that's enough to show that this objection fails.
Still,
though unnecessary, one can point out that saying that the biblical
god is respecting the free choice of the damned to be separated from
him forever is also a gross misrepresentation of the actual
situation: it gives the impression that somehow their freedom is
being respected, while the opposite is the case.
It
would be like saying that the makers of Pig
are
respecting his free choice to be separated from humans or from their
makers.
Alternatively,
we can easily see why their free choice is not being respected by
means of the following scenario:
Let's
suppose that in a distant realm, ruled absolutely by the Emperor, an
imperial decree says that when a person turns eighteen, she has to
choose between declaring herself a servant of the emperor and follow
his commands without question - regardless of what they are -, or be
classified as an undesirable (the decree applies to both men and
women).
Also,
the decree says that anyone who fails to follow a command from the
Emperor is also classified as an undesirable.
The
decree also establishes that a declaration of undesirability is
irreversible, except if the Emperor chooses to make an exception -
but the Emperor promises never to make an exception, and it seems he
always keeps his word -, and that the punishment for undesirability
is to be thrown naked and unarmed into a pit inhabited by a voracious
and cunning monster, which will eat them mostly alive, eating
non-vital organs first.
So,
at eighteen, Luke refuses to serve the Emperor, escapes and joins a
group of rebel fighters. Surely enough, Luke is classified as an
undesirable.
Once
Luke is captured, the Emperor sends a message to the rebels, stating:
"I have chosen to respect the free choice made by your friend
Luke."
So,
the Emperor orders his enforcers to throw Luke into the pit; they
follow the command, and Luke is eaten mostly alive, suffering great
pain in the process and begging for mercy and for a quick death until
he - eventually, but not quickly - dies.
Would
it be sensible to say that the Emperor was just respecting Luke's
free choice not to be a servant of the Emperor's and/or Luke's free
choice to be an undesirable?
I
hope it's clear enough that it would not be so.
Note
that this would not change if the Emperor had instead - for instance
- used advanced technology to make Luke, and had made Luke in a way
such that refusing to serve him would cause Luke great pain for the
rest of his life - which Luke did not know because of some epistemic
mistake -, instead of tossing Luke into a pit with a [another]
monster.
6.4) The evil of Hell
As
we saw in the previous subsection, Hell is a form of infinite
suffering imposed
by the biblical
god on
some people.
I
hope at this point it is clear to the reader how immoral the actions
biblical
god
are:
we're talking about inflicting suffering on people for a thousand
years, then a million years, then a trillion years, and then more -
it just never
ends.
There
is no relief, or hope of relief. They may beg for mercy, or even ask
to be annihilated. But there is no way out for them: they're damned
forever, by the biblical
god.
So,
let's take a look at the objections:
Objection
6.4.1) There is no infinite Hell. That's a mistaken interpretation of
Christianity.
Reply:
As
I pointed out earlier,
versions of Christianity comprising the vast majority of adherents
contend that Hell is infinite, but some claim otherwise, or even deny
that there is Hell at all.
If
a version of Christianity denies that there is infinite Hell - or, at
least, does not affirm that there is -, then it's immune to the
previous points in this section.
However,
some of the points made in earlier
sections
still
show
that
they're not true.
Objection
6.4.2) The people in Hell deserve to suffer forever, for their sins,
and so the biblical god is doing justice by imposing infinite
suffering on them.
Reply:
Even
if one considers some of the worst crimes, like some cases of murder,
rape, rape plus murder, etc., that seems is not true: if someone
commits such actions, arguably they deserve to suffer for that, so
someone might say that they deserve
to suffer for years, or even for decades, or perhaps even for
centuries.
I
don't know what's the maximum they might deserve, but one thing
appears clear: they don't deserve to suffer for
eternity.
One
should, perhaps, stop for a moment and consider what the concept of
Hell entails: It's suffering for millions of years, and then
trillions of years, and then more, and so on. It just never ends.
The
punishment seems clearly infinitely disproportionate even in the case
of the worst criminals.
Objection
6.4.3)The people in Hell deserve to suffer forever, not so much for
adultery, rape or murder - which only merit finite punishment -, but
for the infinite sin of offending (and/or disobeying) a morally
perfect creator, the biblical
god -
who is God.
Reply:
Of
course, one could add the point that, as previous
sections
show,
the biblical
god is
far from being morally perfect, but there is no need for that:
confusing terminology aside, if one ponders the matter carefully, it
should be apparent that disobeying an order from a creator - even if
he were morally perfect -
would
not
make a human being deserving of infinite
suffering.
In
other words, even if God
exists,
then offending
God
simply
does not merit infinite
punishment.
If
one considers this carefully, it should be apparent that the claim
that people actually deserve to go to Hell is in
serious conflict with our sense of right and wrong:
For
example, if the objection were correct, then the normal human moral
outrage against a serial rapist and murderer because
of what he did to their victims -
not to some morally perfect creator -,
would
be completely out of place, since whatever he did to his victims -
for what he might deserve severe but finite punishment - would pale
in comparison with what, say, a shoplifter did to a morally perfect
being - for which the shoplifter would deserve infinite punishment.
The
previous consideration would not be affected by the fact that the
serial rapist and murderer would also deserve infinite punishment for
offending the morally perfect creator - maybe even more than the
shoplifter if somehow he offended him more -, because in that case,
the shoplifter would still deserve infinitely more punishment for
offending the morally perfect creator than
the serial rapist and murderer would deserve for
what he did to the victims of his rapes and murders.
So,
the focus on what the rapist and murderer did to his victims would be
just a complete failure of our moral sense.
Even
most people who have religious beliefs - most people -, and even most
Christians, do react as above.
Incidentally,
many Christians who have pondered the matter seem to have reached the
same conclusion - namely, that humans do not deserve infinite
suffering - and nowadays many Christians reject the idea of an
infinite punishment imposed by the biblical
god,
and instead maintain that Hell is some state chosen by those in Hell,
or that Hell is finite or nonexistent.
While
the view that Hell is finite or nonexistent does avoid the argument
from Hell - though some of the points made in earlier
sections
still
show that those versions of Christianity are not true, either -, the
claim that Hell is chosen by those in Hell is untenable, as we saw in
the
previous
subsection,
Objection
6.4.4) The people in Hell deserve to suffer forever, not so much for
adultery, rape or murder, but for the infinite sin of causing
infinite suffering on a morally perfect creator, who abhors any
wrongdoing, and whose infinite suffering increases with every single
immoral action (or,
as an variant of this objection, with some specific immoral actions).
The
suffering of each of the damned is similar to the suffering he
inflicted on the biblical
god,
who is God.
Reply:
As
usual, there's always the alternative of pointing out that the
biblical
god is
far from being morally perfect, as previous
sections
show,
so he isn't God.
Also,
and for reasons similar to those given above,
this objection too flies in the face of our moral sense, so even if
God
exists,
human do not deserve infinite suffering.
In
addition to that, we can point out the following:
1)
If a being is morally perfect, it does not follow from that that he
will suffer eternally
for
all, or for some immoral actions committed by others.
It
seems a lot more intuitive that if he suffers at all, he suffers only
until the wrongdoer has been adequately punished. Also, the level of
suffering usually resulting from being offended is not remotely
comparable with the level of suffering in Hell, as usually described.
Granted,
someone might claim that the particular morally perfect being that
exists does suffer forever, and as much as someone in Hell does, for
every immoral action anyone commits, but there is no good reason to
assume so, and in fact, there are very good reasons to believe
otherwise (see below).
2)
If a being - say, B - were to suffer for eternity for every single
immoral act that occurs - and with a level of suffering comparable to
that of the people in Hell for every single case -, then freely
carrying out an act of creation from which - he knows
- some
immoral actions will eventually result, would appear to be
a
free choice to be in Hell forever:
He could freely choose not to create - or not to create anything that
would yield that result -, and nothing bad would happen to him as a
result.
So,
it seems clear that it's not a case of negligence if a human does not
factor in - when she acts - the possibility of the suffering of a
being with such a completely alien kind of mind.
To
put a concrete example: intuitively, it's clear that a shoplifter
does not have to factor in the potential infinite suffering of
radically alien invisible beings when she considers whether or not to
shoplift, anymore than she has to consider the possibility that, say,
eating an apple will result in some invisible entity suffering
infinite torment because said entity suffers when someone eats
apples.
While
it's true that she has a moral sense that tells her not to shoplift
but tells her nothing against eating apples, her moral assessment
about shoplifting involve considerations
about the well-being of the owner of the shop, other humans, etc.,
but not of about a being with a radically different kind of mind, who
would freely choose to make morally flawed entities, even though he
knows that that will result in eternal suffering for him.
Similar
considerations apply if the being suffers eternally for some but not
all immoral actions.
3)
If any immoral action by a human merited infinite punishment for
making God
suffer,
then it seems that at
the very least said
human would have to have a reliable means of realizing that that is
the case - or that there is a non-negligible chance of it - before
acting.
In
light of 2), and in light of the considerations given in the reply to
the previous
objection,
that
seems clearly not to be the case.
4)
This objection would have the odd result that the
creator would be in Hell: he would be one of the damned.
In
fact, he would be in the worst kind of Hell, since he would suffer
infinitely and to an extent similar to the suffering of each of the
human damned for
every single one of them.
That
does not appear to be compatible with Christianity at all.
Objection
6.4.5) Our sense of right and wrong cannot be trusted on these
matters, since it's flawed because of the fall. We ought to listen to
the biblical god instead, since his sense of right and wrong is
perfect.
Reply:
That
would amount to simply assume Christianity, instead of assessing
whether it's true.
As
I explained when
replying to preliminary objections,
we can properly use our sense of right and wrong to assess whether a
religion is true, and this objection presents no good reason to
except Christianity from that evaluation.
Objection
6.4.6) Jesus suffered for our sins and died on the cross to save us.
If some people ungratefully reject his offer, it's only fair that
they suffer for eternity.
Reply:
First,
they do not reject any offers.
They
do not believe that there is an offer in the first place.
Even
if they know that there is a claim
made by Christians
that
there is an offer made by Jesus, they do not believe that Jesus is
alive, or making any offers:
Often,
unbelievers - very reasonably - do not believe that preachers live
for thousands of years, and - also, very reasonably - do not believe
that Jesus had any kind of superpowers, or was anything but human.
Obviously,
not all unbelievers are like that. Muslims, for instance, don't
believe in Christianity, but believe that Jesus still exists; but
they too do not believe that there is an offer from Jesus to avoid
Hell by becoming Christians.
Reasonableness
aside, even if there were some epistemic guilt on the part of all
unbelievers;
even if there were some irrationality in reaching the conclusion that
there is no Hell, and/or no offer from Jesus to be accepted or
rejected, etc., the point would remain that they
would not deserve infinite torment for making such an error.
Second,
if the biblical
god chose
to suffer as a means of giving some people a chance to avoid the
infinite torment he
himself would otherwise impose on them,
that's merely another odd quirk of his personality.
But
the fact that the biblical
god suffered
by choice has nothing to do with the fact that human beings do
not deserve to be tormented forever, by whatever means.
Even
if Jesus were giving all humans a chance to avoid eternal punishment
by worshiping him, he would still be coercing
humans into worshiping him under the unjust threat of infinite
torment.
So,
even if some people were actually rejecting his offer, it
wouldn't be fair that
they would suffer for eternity:
Those
few rejecting the offer would be courageous people who would stand up
against a monster who demands worship under the threat of infinite
torment. Perhaps, they would also be foolish because they would have
no chance against the biblical
god's
immense power.
But
what they wouldn't be is deserving of infinite torment just because
they refuse to worship the entity threatening to impose infinite
torment of them.
7)
Conclusion:
In
light of the behavior of the biblical god,
it seems clear that he's not morally good.
Moreover,
if he's a moral agent
at
all - which Christianity seems to maintain [11]-,
he seems to be evil.
Of
course, while this is enough to conclude that Christianity is not
true, that does not entail that the biblical god does not exist.
My
position is that are good reasons to believe that he does not exist,
but that's beyond the scope of this article.
Notes
and references
[1]
Someone
might object to this and say that Christianity is a single religion,
even if Christians sometimes disagree with each other on some
doctrinal issues.
There
is no need to discuss that here, though: whether they're different
religions or one religion with different interpretations, my point is
that I'll try to make arguments that apply to nearly all or all of
those religions and/or interpretations.
[2]
Or,
for that matter, Catholic Tradition, or some other religious book or
source.
I
will focus on the Bible for the sake of brevity, since the reply is
essentially the same in other cases.
[3]
It is true that ancient Hebrew lawmakers - and, perhaps, most ancient
Hebrews - did not make such assessments. That fact, however, is not
problematic, as I will explain later,
when consider a specific objection.
[4]
One could also mention the fact that looking at the hymen is an
unreliable method of ascertaining whether a woman has had sex, or
that she might have been raped but the rape wasn't proved, etc.
However,
there is no need for that, as the command would still be immoral -
and the claim or implication that she deserves to be stoned to death
false -, even if the method were reliable.
[5] The Catholic "New
American Bible" includes whipping him as part of the punishment.
[6] Of course, if one puts aside
for a moment the assumption that the biblical
god exists and assesses the evidence properly, the conclusion is
that he does not exist, and the monsters were the human writers of
that law.
[7] Someone might suggest or
claim that chimpanzees, bonobos and a few other non-human animals are
moral agents. But the law is not limited to
those animals.
Further,
there were no such animals in the territories were the ancient
Hebrews lived.
[8] I included this objection
after a Christian I was talking to actually raised it.
But
it's hard to see how people from our time and with at least an
average level of education in a developed country can seriously say
that the non-human animals may have been possessed by demons.
Then
again, they believe that an entity with superhuman powers gave the
ancient Hebrews the law, that Jesus resurrected, and they raise a
number of other absurd objections to arguments against Christianity -
including some of the ones I'm considering -, so I guess one
shouldn't be surprised by this particular one after all.
[9]
Of
course, that his commands and claims resemble the brutality of their
society is no surprise if one assesses the evidence properly and
concludes that there was no biblical
god
giving
those commands, but were made up precisely by some of the leaders of
their society.
However,
as long as we keep the assumption that the
biblical
god
did
it,
the
conclusion is that his actions were unacceptable.
[10] Catechism of the Catholic
Church, 1033-1037.
Source:
http://www.vatican.va/archive/ENG0015/__P2O.HTM
It's
true that the Catholic Church also claims that Hell is freely chosen
by those in Hell, but that claim is untenable.
[11]
Even
if some Christian philosophers maintain that he's not a moral agent
because - allegedly - "morally good" when applied to God
does not mean what's usually meant by "morally good", and
the biblical god
is
God, that would not be a
successful objection to this moral case.