This post is out of date. An improved reply to the KCA can be found here.
The
Kalam Cosmological Argument Still Provides no Support for Theism
a)
In a article
I posted earlier, I argued that the Kalam Cosmological Argument
(KCA) does
not provide any support for theism.
This
article is for the most part similar to that one, but with some
modifications, especially to address Craig's
reply to one of my previous objections.
I
posted a brief
reply to Craig's reply earlier, but I decided to post a new full
argument, addressing the matter in more detail.
Also,
I've added some new points, remove a few I think were superfluous,
and introduced some modifications in the structure of the post and in
some of the arguments.
b)
The premises of the KCA are: [0]
P1:
Everything that begins to exist has a cause.
P2:
The universe began to exist.
William
Lane Craig and other theists offer a number of arguments in support
of the premises of the KCA, concluding that the universe has a cause.
Then, they provide further arguments in support of the claim that the
cause is God.
In
the
second
section, I
will prove
a more general result about the incompatibility of a tensed theory of
time and the timeless existence of God.
In
those two sections, for the sake of the argument I will not challenge
the concept of timelessness as used in the Kalam Cosmological
Argument.
Later,
I will address Craig's reply to the
objection to the KCA that I raise in the first two sections - more
precisely, his reply to the objection I raised in the first two
sections of a
previous version of this argument, but the objection is
essentially the same.
Leaving
aside the objection I mentioned above, I will later
challenge on different grounds the claim that God is timeless sans
the universe but temporal with it.
In
other sections, I will raise other objections to the KCA, as well as
to the added conclusion - even assuming that the universe had a cause
of its existence - that the cause is God.
In
most of this article, I will focus on William Lane Craig's version of
the KCA, given that that is the most common one.
However,
I will also address several potential alternatives, showing that they
provide no support for theism, either.
On
a terminological note, I will use the word “argument”
loosely, to refer to both the formal argument, and the informal
arguments used to support the premises of the formal argument. I
think this is a common way of speaking, and context should prevent
any ambiguity despite some notational abuse.
William
Lane Craig and J. P. Sinclair[2]:
By
an “event,” one means any change. Since any change takes
time, there are no instantaneous events so defined. Neither could
there be an infinitely slow event, since such an “event”
would, in reality, be a changeless state. Therefore, any event will
have a finite, nonzero duration.
William
Lane Craig[3]
The
reason I hold God to be timeless without the universe is that I think
that an infinite regress of events is impossible, and, according to a
relational theory of time, in the absence of any events time would
not exist. The reason I hold God to be temporal since the beginning
of the universe is that the creation of the universe brings God into
a new relation, namely, co-existing with the universe, and such an
extrinsic change alone (not to mention God’s exercise of causal
power) is sufficient for a temporal relation.
William
Lane Craig[4]
So
if God is timeless, he is also unchanging, but it does not follow
that He cannot change. I’d say that He can change and if He
were to do so, He would cease to be timeless. And that’s
exactly what I think He did.
God
changes from timeless to
temporal.
Any
change is an event,
so
let E(0)
be the event “God changes from being timeless to being
temporal”.[5].
Now,
if t=0 is the beginning of time, then E(0) is an event that ends
at
t=0, since t=0 is the first time at which God is temporal.
Since
every event has a finite, non-zero duration, E(0) has some duration
e>0, and ends at t=0.
Then,
there is a time interval of duration e prior to t=0.
I
will address Craig's reply to this objection in more detail later,
but in light of that reply, let's clarify a few points:
First, Craig did not
define "change" at all.
Instead,
he defined "event" as "any change", using
"change" in the usual sense of the word, and claimed
that any change takes time.
So, I'm in no way
confusing different senses of "change".
Rather, I'm using
the examples of God's changing from timeless to temporal, God
changing from not knowing any tensed truths to knowing some tensed
truths, etc., and showing that a contradiction follows from Craig's
position.
Second, the quotes
in which Craig claims that God changed from timeless to temporal are
useful to illustrate the contradiction, but not at all required to
make my point.
In fact, it follows
from Craig's claims that - for instance - there is some state of the
world S at which God does not know any tensed truths - because there
are no tensed facts at S -, followed by a state of the world at which
God does know at least one tensed truth.
So, God actually changed from not knowing any tensed truths, to knowing some tensed truths or - if one prefers - the state of the world changed, from a state at which there is no entity that knows any tensed truths, to a state at which there is at least one entity that knows at least one tensed truth.
So, God actually changed from not knowing any tensed truths, to knowing some tensed truths or - if one prefers - the state of the world changed, from a state at which there is no entity that knows any tensed truths, to a state at which there is at least one entity that knows at least one tensed truth.
Third, even if one
puts aside the claim that the changes in question have a non-zero,
finite duration, one can consider - as I did above - both cases:
If the changes are
instantaneous - i.e., their duration is zero -, then a contradiction
follows.
If the changes, on
the other hand, take time - i.e., their duration is greater than zero
-, then a contradiction follows.
One way or another,
a contradiction follows.
Fourth, as it should
be clear, none of the above requires that one define "event"
as Craig does.
Again, it suffices
to point out that if the changes in question are instantaneous, a
contradiction follows, and if it's not instantaneous, a contradiction
follows, anyway.
Fifth, in case
someone claims that the changes are somehow timeless, or partly
timeless, I will point out that uttering the word "timeless"
does not constitute a "get out of logic free" card.
What would "timeless
change" even mean?
I
will address those issues in greater detail when I address Craig's
reply to my objection.
2)
A tensed theory of time entails that it's not the case that the
actual world contains a state of affairs S at which God exists
timelessly
Let's
assume, under a tensed theory of time, that the actual world contains
a state of affairs S at which God exists timelessly.
At
S, God does not have any knowledge of tensed truths - if he did, he
would know that some events are past (or
present), and
then God's state would not be timeless; if some events are past at S,
then S is past or present.
Yet,
today, God knows tensed truths: he knows, for instance, that World
War Two has already ended.
So,
we can consider the event E(2):
“God changes from not having any knowledge of tensed facts, to
knowing some tensed truths”.
Since
E(2) is an event, it has a duration e>0, and ends at some time t1.
If
there is a time t2 < t1, then God does not yet have knowledge of
tensed facts. However, there are tensed facts. But that's impossible.
Therefore,
there is no time earlier that t1.
But
then, given that E(2) is an event of duration e > 0 that ends at
t1, there is an interval of duration e that comes before t1,
contradicting the conclusion that there is no time
earlier than t1.
Someone
might object that, perhaps, there are events that have a zero
duration, after all, and that E(2) is one such event.
Let's
suppose that the event E(2), which ends at t1, and has duration 0.
Then,
since E(2) ends at t1, then its beginning is also at t1. Hence, at
t1, it is not the case that God has knowledge of any tensed facts –
since the event starts at t1 -, but also, at t1, God has knowledge of
some tensed facts – since the event ends at t1. But that is
impossible.
So,
this objection fails.
Another
objection might be that E(2) does not start at t1, but at timeless
state S.
However,
using the word "timeless" does not allow one to get around
logic: if the event E(2) ends at a time t=t1, and its duration is
actually zero, it follows its beginning is also present at
t=t1.
Finally,
as a desperate move, I suppose that someone might try something like
"The concept of duration doesn't apply to E(2), because E(2) is
a partially timeless event".
As
I pointed out earlier, the
word "timeless" does not constitute a "get out of
logic free" card.
What does "timeless
change" even mean?
I
will address that problem in greater detail when I address Craig's
reply to my previous objection,
but the conclusion is that if a tensed theory of time is true, the
actual world contains no state of affairs at which God exists
timelessly.
Also,
the previous reasoning does not depend on other assumptions about
time that Craig makes, such as relationalism or an intrinsic metric,
or whether presentism or a "growing-block" theory is true.
In
the cases of relationalism vs. substantivalism, as well as
"growing-block" vs. presentism, it's clear that they're
orthogonal to the previous points, which don't mention any of the
contentious issues.
As
for a metric, if there is no intrinsic metric, the duration of E(2)
would depend on the metric, and that would be conventional.
However,
the fact that E(2) has a non-zero duration would not: on
metric relativism about time, events still have a positive, nonzero
duration; the previous reasoning against E(2) having a zero duration
holds - and assuming a zero duration would still yield a
contradiction, using the same argument as before.
An
alternative way of seeing this is that, even on metric
conventionalism, there still is a relation of before and after;
moreover, on conventionalism, it's changes that
determine before and after.
So,
the beginning of the event E(2) would still happen before
the end of it, and so there would be a time prior to t1 contradicting
the conclusion that there is no time prior to t=t1.
So,
in brief, if a tensed theory of time is true, then it's not the case
that the actual world contains a state of affairs at which God exists
timelessly.
3)
A tensed theory of time and the first premise of the KCA together
entail that either there is a beginningless infinite regress of
events, or God does not exist
The
first premise of the KCA states that everything that begins to exist,
has a cause.
While
I don't think that Craig's understanding of the terms [8]
matches
the usual meaning of “comes into being”, or the meaning
of "begins to exist", I will assume Craig's understanding
of the meanings in this section.[9]
So,
let's assume a tensed theory of time, and suppose that the first
premise is true and God exists.
Since
God does not have a cause, he does not have a beginning.
Since
the
actual
world contains no state of affairs at which God exists timelessly,
then there is no first time t at which God exists.
So,
it follows that for every time t, there is a time u < t, such that
God exists at u. [10]
Now,
at t, God has knowledge of at least one tensed truth that he does not
know at u: namely, that u is past, and t is present. In other words,
God's knowledge of tensed truths is upgraded as time goes by,
regardless of whether there is any other change in any other entity.
So,
if u < t, then we can consider the event E(u,t): “God comes
to know that u is past, and t is present”.[11]
Therefore,
considering a sequence of times t(k), for every natural number k, in
which t(k+1) < t(k), and considering that God exists at t(k) for
every natural number k, we can conclude that there are infinitely
many events E((k+1),k)), for every natural number k.
From
the way the sequence is constructed, it's clear that it has no
beginning point; moreover, since God does not begin to exist and
doesn't exist timelessly, there is no t=0.
Also,
in the previous arguments in this section, no assumption other than a
tensed theory of time and the first premise of the KCA were made.
In
particular, the result is independent of the issues time
relationalism vs. substantivalism, intrinsic metric vs. metric
conventionalism, and presentism vs. "growing-block" theory.
On
the other hand, if there is an intrinsic metric of time and any
entity with a metric-finite past begins to exist, then under these
assumptions (i.e., the first premise of the KCA, plus a tensed theory
of time), either there is a metric-infinite past, or God does not
exist - since God did not begin to exist and doesn't exist
timelessly.
4)
Assuming a tensed theory of time, arguments
against an infinite regress of events do not provide any support for
theism in the context of the KCA[12]
William
Lane Craig provides two philosophical arguments intended to show that
an infinite regress of events is metaphysically impossible, and in
that way support the second premise of the KCA.
However,
neither the first nor the second argument, nor any other argument
against such possibility, provide any support for theism in the
context of the KCA[12],
and
under a tensed theory of time.
In
fact, given the result of section
3,
on a tensed theory of time, if such an infinite regress of events is
impossible - or just not actual
-,
then either the first premise of the KCA is false, or God does not
exist.
Thus,
no argument intended to establish that an infinite regress of events
is logically or metaphysically impossible, or even that there is no
such regress in the actual world, can help a theistic case based on
the KCA.
This
result is general in the sense that it's not limited to Craig's
particular philosophical arguments, and also in that it does not
depend on assumptions such as time relationalism, an intrinsic metric
of time, or presentism - since the result of section
3 does
not depend on any such assumptions, either.
It
still uses Craig's understanding of "begins to exist", but
later I will show that alternative
readings of "begis to exist" do not help a case for theism,
either.
5)
Assuming a tensed theory of time, modern cosmology does not support
theism in the context of the KCA[12]
In
addition to the two philosophical arguments, Craig maintains that
modern (scientific) cosmology supports the second premise of the KCA.
However, that's not our concern in this section.
The
issue is whether, if that were true, that would provide support for
theism in this context.
If
a cosmological model entails an infinite regress of events[13]
in the universe, and
a beginning point, that's incompatible with a tensed theory of time,
since an infinity can't be reached by finite successive addition from
a beginning point.
Note
that that does not depend on whether the events are of equal
duration. Even if they are increasingly short, and even if the
infinite series converges, it seems one couldn't engage in an
infinite addition - any number of finite steps would remain finite.
If
a cosmological model entails that there is only a finite regress of
past events and a beginning at some time t=0, then in light of
section
three, a theist who supports a tensed theory of time and the
first premise of the KCA ought to accept, on pain of inconsistency,
that there are infinitely many events prior to the beginning of the
universe.
But
if so, someone might posit a multiverse, megaverse, older universe -
or whatever one calls it - as a possible candidate to be the cause of
the universe - i.e., as an alternative to God.
Cosmological
models of the universe do not contain a claim that a beginning of
what they call “the universe” is also a beginning without
any previous universes, multiverses, etc., and the second premise of
the KCA does not provide any support for theism if "universe"
is understood in a restrictive sense, excluding older universes,
multiverses, etc.
So,
this attempt to support theism using scientific cosmology fails.
A
possibility that we still need to consider is a scientific model with
a metric-finite past but with an infinite regress of past events in
the universe, and no beginning point.
Under
such model, and under the main alternative
understandings of "begins to exist", the universe did
not begin to exist, so that would be of no help for the KCA.
However,
under Craig's understanding of "begins
to exist", the universe did begin to exist in that case.
There
are, however, insurmountable problems for the theist defender of the
KCA under this hypothesis.
For
instance, under
these conditions, a metric-finite
past entails a beginning of existence.
Hence,
if God exists, then he does not have a finite past, since he did not
begin to exist.
That
entails that if God exists, he existed at some time t before
the infinitely regress of past
events in the metric-finite past of the universe occurred. That means
that, from t to, say, the year 2000, an infinite progress
of events has happened, by
finite successive addition and from a beginning point, which is
impossible under a tensed theory. Hence,
God does not exist. So, this road is closed to the theist as well.
6)
Alternative readings of "begins to exist" do not support a
case for theism in the context of the KCA[12]
I
will analyze two alternatives, and conclude that they provide no such
support.
While
I can't rule out that someone might come up with a different
alternative, it seems to me they would probably include highly
counterintuitive scenarios like two-coordinate time, or
undifferentiated time, etc. - the usual ones seem to be covered.
If
so, it's not clear that we would have any reliable intuitions about
causation in such scenarios - apart from the fact that that would
probably not match any common usage, either -, so it's not clear how
they would derive support for the first premise.
So,
it seems to me that the following two variants cover most ground
(and, in any case, the burden would be on someone who proposes an
alternative reading).
6.1)
First alternative reading
On
this reading, "B begins to exist" is understood as meaning
the same as "B comes into being" - as Craig claims -, but
"B comes into being" (and so, "B begins to exist")
is not understood in the sense posited by Craig, but in the sense
that there is an event "B comes into existence" -
i.e., a change from a state of
affairs at which B does not exist, to one at which B does exist.
On
this understanding of "B begins to exist", a first moment
of the universe would not entail the universe began to exist.
In
order for the universe to begin to exist, there would have to be a
change from a state at which the universe does not exist, to one at
which it does.
Moreover,
that state of affairs at which the universe does not exist would have
to be something other than a multiverse, etc. - "universe"
in the second premise has to be understood broadly, including such
multiverses; else, someone might always posit an older universe,
multiverse, etc., blocking the argument to theism,
Modern
cosmology makes no claims about that kind of state and/or event, and
even if an argument established that an infinite regress of events is
logically or metaphysically impossible, or that at least there is no
such infinite regress in the actual world, that alone would not
entail that the actual world contains a state at which no universe,
multiverse, etc., exists, and then an event "the universe comes
into existence".
Someone
could try to establish such state and event by means of other kinds
of arguments - say, a contingency argument, or an argument to design
-, and then draw support for theism from that.
I
don't believe any such argument succeeds; however, if one such
argument were successful, it would be inaccurate to say that the KCA
provides any support for theism. Rather, the fact would be that the
other argument provides support both for theism, and for the second
premise of the KCA as well.
So,
the conclusion is that this alternative reading of "begins to
exist" does not help a case for theism in the context of the
KCA[12],
either.
The
results of this subsection make no special assumptions about a theory
of time; so, they hold regardless of whether relationalism is true,
whether time has an intrinsic metric, or even whether a tensed theory
of time is true.
Another
alternative reading - which I think is the closest match of the
meaning of the words; see section
10 for
more details - would be:[14]
A.
x begins to exist at [t1,t2] iff there is a finite closed interval
[t1,t2] such that x does not exist at any time prior to t1, and x
exists at t2.
B.
x comes into being iff there is an event
-
that
is, change - from a state of affairs at which x does not exist, to a
state of affairs at which it does.
I
will address the matter of whether belief in the first premise is
justified in section
eleven,
but for the moment let us assume, for the sake of the argument, that
it is justified under this understanding of "begins to exist".
Could
the KCA be used to support theism, then?
The
answer is still no:
under
this understanding of "begins to exist", all the relevant
results of sections three,
four
and
five
can
be derived as well, by means of essentially the same reasoning, and
just the obvious, minor adaptations. For the sake of brevity, I will
not repeat those points here.
The
previous sections show that, under Craig's reading of "begins to
exist":
a)
Craig's version of the KCA provides no support for theism.
b)
Assuming a tensed theory of time, dropping assumptions like an
intrinsic metric of time, time relationalism or presentism does not
help a case for theism, either.
c)
In general, assuming a tensed theory of time, arguments against the
logical and/or the metaphysical possibility of an infinite regress of
events - or even against the existence of such regress in the actual
world - would not help the theist's case, either.
d)
Arguments allegedly based on science do not provide support for
theism in this context, either.
That
seems to leave no possibilities left, at least assuming a tensed
theory of time, and Craig's reading of "begins to exist".
Moreover,
assuming a tensed theory of time, section
6 shows
that two alternative readings of the first premise would not help a
case for theism, either: Those readings seem to cover most possible
non-unusual readings.
So,
the previous sections show that, on a tensed theory of time, the KCA
provides no support for theism.
At
this point, there appears to be no options left to consider, if one
accepts Craig's assertion that a tensed theory of time is a requisite
for the KCA
[15].
Still,
one need not agree with Craig on that, so let's assess whether
someone could assume a tenseless theory of time, and then use the KCA
to support theism.
On
a tenseless theory, and going by Craig's understanding of "begins
to exist", then the second premise of the KCA is not true.
As
a matter of fact, on a tenseless theory of time, nothing
begins
to exist in
the
sense of "begins to exist"
proposed by Craig,
since there are no tensed facts.
On
the other hand, under the first
alternative reading of
the first premise considered above, things can begin to exist on a
tenseless theory of time.
However,
under
that reading, the KCA provides no support for theism, even under a
tenseless theory of time.
So,
let's consider an argument based on the second
alternative reading of "begins to exist",
assuming a tenseless theory of time.
Would
a variant of the KCA based on that reading provide any support for
theism?
I
will argue in the section
eleven that
belief in the first premise is not justified, anyway, but that's
another matter.
Here,
the question is whether - granting both a tenseless theory and the
first premise under the second
alternative reading
-,
the KCA provides support for theism.
It
seems not:
On
a tenseless theory of time, it appears that the past, the present and
the future are ontologically equivalent.
So,
it seems then that any successful argument for the metaphysical (or
logical) necessity of a beginning of time could be adapted to be an
argument for the metaphysical (or logical) necessity of an end of
time.
Hence,
a theist attempting this line of argumentation ought to accept that,
necessarily, if God exists, he will eventually become still
and never act again.
Of
course, if a theist also holds that God exists necessarily, she ought
to accept that, necessarily, God will eventually become still and
never act again.
That
necessity could be metaphysical or logical depending on the case, but
given usual descriptions of God, it's hard to see a way around that
in either case, even if the precise moment at which the end of time
will happen is still a contingent matter.
But
let's say that that is not a problem after all. Even then, it seems
intuitively clear that there is no contradiction involved in the
claim of an infinite future progress of events.
Also,
there appears to be no intuitive support for the idea that the future
is closed in that way - in fact, that's highly counterintuitive -, so
attempts to use intuitions to show metaphysical impossibility would
fail just for that reason, independently of other considerations
about such arguments.
Perhaps,
an alternative would be for a theist to argue for the claim that even
if a beginning of time may not be logically or metaphysically
necessary, it is at least factual.
However,
that kind of argument would have to be empirical, and there is no
support in present-day cosmology for such a claim: even if a
scientific model posited no infinite regress of events the universe
in a very narrow sense of the word "universe",
they would probably make no claim about an entire series of past
events, which might comprise an older universe, multiverse, etc.
After
someone raised the issue on his website, Craig replied[16]
to the objection I
raised in section
one of an earlier version of my argument -
which is the same I've raised in section
one of this article, though I provided a shorter explanation of
my objection in the earlier version.
Craig
replied that God's gaining knowledge of tensed facts (for instance)
does not qualify as an event, since it's "instantaneous".
[16]
That
aside, let's continue analyzing Craig's reply to my objection:
William
Lane Craig[16]
First,
Craig does not restrict the range of 'event' at all in his
definition, and so he gave no reason for restricting the range at
all. Instead, he defined
'event' as 'any
change', and then argued
from
there, that any event will have a finite, non-zero duration. So, the
'restriction' is a consequence
of his reasoning, not
a stipulative
definition.
That
is obvious in the quotation from his
book I gave for context (due to copyright reasons, I may not post
long parts of his book, but that part suffices to make that clear; of
course, I invite readers to take a look at his book more closely in
case of any doubt)
Second,
that
changes take time to occur is precisely one of my points, which I use
to derive a contradiction on Craig's position.
In
fact, he claimed that there are no instantaneous events precisely
because any change takes time, and he defined "event"
as "any change".
So,
I pointed out that the change
- for instance -
from
a state S at which God does not know any tensed truths (because there
aren't any tensed facts), to a state at which God knows some tensed
truths (at t=0) is, well, a change,
and changes take time to occur - as Craig stated -, from which a
contradiction follows.
But let's see a
little more of the reply:
William
Lane Craig[16]
Similarly,
God’s coming to believe all tensed truths would not qualify as
an event, since it, too, happens instantaneously.
But
that is obviously false. Since it's a change, then it follows - by
his own definition - that it's an event.
In
fact, by claiming that it's instantaneous, Craig is only
contradicting
his own claim that all changes take time. Once
again, this is obvious from my
previous quotation on his book.
Yet,
in his reply to the objection I raised, Craig claims
[16]
that
God's gaining knowledge of tensed facts is instantaneous, and
therefore it's not a change in God in "this technical sense".
But
there
is no such "this technical sense" of "change" in
Craig's KCA, since - as
we can see in his book - Craig
did
not
define
"change" at all.
The
only sense of 'change' is the usual sense of 'change' in English; in
other words, he left 'change' undefined, used the usual concept in
order to define "event" - as is apparent in the quote above
-, and then argued from there -
keeping in mind the usual meaning of 'change' -, that any change
takes time.
Of
course, God's change from not knowing any tensed truths to knowing at
least some tensed truths is, well, a change
in
the usual sense of the word 'change' in English, and by
Craig's own reasoning, we can conclude that it takes time, and
thus derive a contradiction, as I
did above.
So,
in short, Craig did not define
"events"
as having zero duration. Neither did he define "change" as
having a non-zero duration, or at all. Instead, he defined "event"
as "any change", and assessed
that
events/changes have non-zero duration, as the
previous quotation from his book shows
(once again, I invite readers interested in more details can take a
look at his book and see more context for themselves). Yet, the
changes I'm talking about are obviously changes in the usual sense of
the word "change" in English - which is the one he was
using in the context of the KCA -, and assuming that they have a
non-zero duration, a contradiction follows as
explained
(I
will later show that, in any case, a
contradiction follows regardless of whether we assume that the
changes take time or are instantaneous).
In
addition to the previous claims, in his reply
to my objection, Craig contends that in the second
and third quotations, he was using "change" in a
different sense from the sense in which he used the word in the
context of the KCA, and that in those second
and third quotations, he "merely" meant that God does
not have the same properties in his timeless state as he does in his
first temporal state[16].
But an analysis of
his words show that he clearly did not merely
meant that - that is only part of what he meant.
In fact, Craig said
that God changed from timeless to temporal, and ceased
to be timeless.
He did not say hat
God changed from temporal to timeless, or that he
ceased to be timeless - clearly, that would not have meant the
same, and Craig himself does not accept the possibility of change
from temporal to timeless.
So,
when Craig said that God had changed - in the second
and third quotations - he did not merely meant that God in his
timeless state has different properties from God in his first
temporal state.
The claim of a
change is not only a claim that the properties differ, but there is
also a direction: God has some properties in his timeless
state, and changes and has some other properties in his first
temporal state: it goes in one direction, not the other.
In other words, the
change is from the timeless to the temporal state, not vice versa, so
what he meant is not merely that God's properties in his
timeless state are different from his properties in his first
temporal state: change is not directionless.
So,
that still
is
the usual sense of "change" in English, as he used in his
book, in the Kalam Cosmological Argument, as far as one can tell from
his statements.
So, in brief:
a) Craig's claim
that he used 'change' in a technical sense in his book, is a false
claim. He used it in the ordinary sense of the words.
b)
Craig's claim that he used 'changed' to merely say that God has
different properties in his timeless and first temporal states, is
also false.
Once
again, he used 'changed' in the ordinary sense of the words in
English.
c)
The fact remains that a
contradiction follows from Craig's position.
That
aside, Craig also maintains[16] that in
any case, one can change the definition of "event" in the
second premise of the Kalam Cosmological Argument and clarify that
the events in question are events of non-zero, finite, equal
duration. Actually, if he did that, he would be withdrawing his claim
that any change takes time, rather than merely clarifying his claims.
However, that is a
side point.
The
crucial point is that if we do that, or if we we make, for the sake
of the argument, the false assumption that Craig said what he later
claimed he had said, a
contradiction still follows.
In fact, a
contradiction can be derived without any assumptions about what Craig
said, as the next subsection shows.
In this subsection:
a) By 'event' I mean
the same as 'change'.
b) By 'P(2)' I mean
the property of knowing at least one tensed truth.
c) By 'E(2)' I mean
the event/change 'God changes from not having P(2) to having P(2) for
the first time'.
d) By 'S' I mean the
allegedly timeless state of God, at which God does not have P(2).
e) By 't=0' I mean
the first temporal state of the world - and of God.
If E(2) has a
duration e>0, then since E(2) finished at t=0, there is a temporal
interval of duration e>0, prior to t=0. But that is a
contradiction.
If E(2) has a zero
duration, then since the final state of E(2) - namely, the state of
God's having property P(2) for the first time - obtains at t=0, and
the duration of E(2) is actually zero, then the initial state of E(2)
- a state at which it is not the case that God has property P(2) -
also obtains at t=0.
Hence, at t=0, God
has property P(2), and it is not the case that God has property P(2).
But that is a contradiction.
Someone might object
that the initial state of E(2) is not present at t=0, but at timeless
state S, and the final state is present at t=0.
However,
my point here is that if the end of the event of zero duration is at
t=0, and the duration is, well, zero,
then the conclusion
is
that the beginning of the event is at t=0 as well, entailing a
contradiction.
In brief:
1)
If E(2) has a non-zero duration - which follows from Craig's
original claim, in this book -, then a contradiction follows.
2)
If E(2) is instantaneous - which is what
Craig says in his reply to my objection -, then a contradiction
follows.
The contradiction is
inescapable.
Note that even if
Craig chooses to use the word 'change' in a non-standard way, and no
longer calls that change in God (and it's a change in the ordinary
sense of the word 'change') a change, that is irrelevant to my point.
I'm using 'change' in the ordinary sense, and showing that a
contradiction follows anyway.
I guess Craig or
someone else might then claim that those changes - and they are
changes, in the usual sense of the word 'change' in English - do not
have either a zero duration, or a non-zero duration, but somehow
they're timeless or partially timeless, and somehow for that
so-called 'reason' one shouldn't speak of duration.
But
if they did that,
I would first point out that Craig claimed that the first cause is -
at least in his timeless state, 'sans the universe' -,
changeless.[17]
In addition, I would
take issue with the meaningfulness of his claims:
Craig claims that
the changes are 'instantaneous', but somehow they don't have a zero
duration?
What does Craig even
mean, then, by 'instantaneous', if not 'having a zero duration'?
Moreover, how are
those changes are somehow 'timeless' or 'partially timeless' changes?
What would that even
mean?
If
by "X is timeless", Craig means that X does not stand in
any temporal relations, then the problem remains: how can an object
exist in the first state of the world, and then change, and still
be
timeless in that first state, given that it seems it does
not differ from a temporal state at t=0?
And
if "timelessness" is something like "absence of all
events" (i.e., an absence of all changes), then there cannot be
a timeless change, so the changes I take into consideration either
have a non-zero duration (and so, a
contradiction follows)
or a zero duration (and still, a
contradiction follows).
In
fact, as I pointed out above, Craig himself contends that God, in his
timeless state, is changeless.
[17],
so
'timeless change' (if meaningful at all) would also contradict
Craig's claims.
What if Craig means
something else by 'timeless'?
In any case,
'timeless change' is not an option, by Craig's own words.
Regardless, let's
leave the previous contradictions aside in this subsection for a
moment, and show that, in any case, a 'timeless' God who becomes
temporal is an untenable claim: more precisely, the reason the
contradictions can derived is that what he proposes is actually
ontologically indistinguishable from God at t=0, even though he calls
the state 'timeless' and denies that it's t=0, so he's describing a
first temporal state, and yet denying that it's temporal.
Let's consider two
scenarios, ordering the states of the world in terms of the direction
given by supporters of the KCA - i.e., the world changes from one
state to the next.
First
state of the world:
Timeless
state S. The only object is O, which exists uncaused.
Second
state of the world:
Temporal
state. t=0. The objects are O and U, and O is the cause of the
existence of U; they all exist temporally at t=0.
Third
state of the world:
Temporal
state; t=r > 0. The objects are O, U and, perhaps some other
objects.
Scenario
2:
First
state of the world:
t=0.
The only object is O, which exists uncaused.
Second
state of the world:
Temporal
state. t=a>0. The objects are O and U, and O is the cause of the
existence of U.
Third
state of the world:
Temporal
state; t=r > a. The objects are O, U and, perhaps some other
objects.
A
key question here is: What is the ontological difference
between the two?
Saying
that one has a timeless state and the other does not, so that is the
ontological difference, would miss the point:
The
point is that this so-called "timeless" state seems to
behave exactly like a temporal state at t=0, even if the word
"timeless" is deployed.
In
other words, there is no ontological difference, even if
different words - of very dubious meaningfulness to say the
least - are used.
Furthermore,
on the issue of timelessness, Craig makes the following claim:
William
Lane Craig: [2]
If
not, then since the universe cannot ever
have existed in an absolutely quiescent state, the universe must have
had a beginning.
In
which sense can object O be in an “absolutely quiescent”
state in scenario 1, but not in scenario 2?
In
both cases, what we have is one first state of affairs that changes
into another state of affairs.
How
would any of them be any more "quiescent" than the other?
It
seems clear that that cannot be so: in both cases, O just changes
from the first state to the second.
O
never remains unchanged for a while -
which would require time.
The
mere uttering of words like "quiescent" or "timeless"
is not a "get out of logic free" card, and should not be
accepted as making a distinction that is not there.
Given
the previous considerations, it seems clear that the "timeless"
claim amounts to trying to make an exception to the premise that
everything that begins to exist, has a cause of its existence, just
by using the word "timeless", but failing to actually
denote any ontological differences...
10)
The meaning of "begins to exist"
While
the results of the previous sections show that the KCA provides no
support for theism, there are further, independent
and
conclusive reasons to reject it.
In
the this and the following sections, I will provide sufficient
reasons to conclude that the KCA provides no
support
for theism, even if all of the arguments I gave so far were to be
rejected.
In
this section, I will assess the meaning of "begins to exist";
first, let's
compare Craig's hypothesis about the
meanings of "begins to exist" and "comes into being",
with the second alternative reading
considered in section six
(let's call this
alternative hypothesis "hypothesis 2") [14],
and
test the two hypothesis to see which one is closer to matching the
meaning of the words.
A.
x begins to exist at [t1,t2] iff there is a finite closed interval
[t1,t2] such that x does not exist at any time prior to t1, and x
exists at t2.
B.
x comes into being iff there is an event
- that
is, change - from a state of affairs at which x does not exist, to a
state of affairs at which it does. .
Under
a tensed theory of time, everyday examples will not help us test one
vs. the other, since both hypotheses yield the same results.
However,
under a tenseless theory of time, the difference is striking:
Let's
assume a tenseless theory, and let's consider, for instance,
Napoleon.
It
seems clear that, even if the past, present and future exist
tenselessly, there is a time at which Napoleon did not exist, and a
later time at which he did.
So,
it seems to me that he came into being,
and began to exist. That's
in line with hypothesis 2.
On
the other hand, under Craig's hypothesis, assuming a tenseless theory
of time, nothing begins
to exist, and nothing comes into being.
In
particular, Napoleon neither came into being, nor began to exist. But
that seems clearly conceptually wrong.
In
fact, the questions of whether a tensed theory is true and whether
Napoleon came into being, or began to exist, appear to be orthogonal.
It
seems rather odd that Craig would include tense in the definition of
"begins to exist", but he argues that, under a tenseless
theory of time, a universe with a first event did not begin to exist
just as a meter stick does not begin to exist just because it has a
first centimeter.[18]
That
argument is odd as well, though:
While
a meter stick does not begin to exist
in virtue of having a first centimeter,
that's not relevant, since having a first centimeter is a spatial,
not a temporal
claim, while "begins to exist" - at least, in this context
- is clearly about time, not space.
In
fact, the stick in question does
have a beginning
in space because
it has a
first centimeter, and similarly, even if a tenseless theory of 7time
is true, the stick does have a beginning
in time
as long
as there is, say, a first year
at which it exists.
It
is true that, in order for us to say a year is first,
we need to pick an order in time - from past to future, not the other
way around, but that direction is actually implicitly built-in
hypothesis 2, and in our language about time.
Also,
to say that the stick has a spatial beginning require that one picks
a direction in space to say which centimeter is first - in this case,
explicitly or by context.
A
difference is that, in the case of space, one needs to pick the
direction explicitly or by context, whereas in the case of time, it's
built in the meaning of the words, but that does not appear to be
relevant to the point that there is a beginning.
Since
to say that the stick begins to exist - in the sense that's relevant
in the context of the KCA, at least - is the same as to say that the
stick has a temporal beginning, or a beginning in time, then it
follows that the stick does begin to exist, even on a tenseless
theory of time.
Then,
it seems to me that hypothesis 2 gives the right result, whereas
Craig's hypothesis does not.
Let's
consider a different scenario; scenario S1:
Let
us suppose that there is a t=0, and an entity B that exists at t=0.
Let us suppose that there is no time earlier than t=0. Let's further
suppose that there is no state of the world at which B does not
exist, and the actual world does not contain any timeless states of
affairs whatsoever, or any kind of two-coordinates time, or
undifferentiated time, or any such temporally counterintuitive state
of affairs[19].
Does
B begin to exist?
Does B come into being?
Does B come into being?
According
to Craig's hypothesis, if a tensed theory is time is true, then B
begins to exist and comes into being, whereas if a tenseless theory
of time is true, then B neither begins to exist nor comes into being.
On
the other hand, according to hypothesis 2, regardless of the tensed
vs. tenseless issue, B does begin to exist, but does not come into
being.
Readers
will use their own intuitive grasp of the words, of course, but mine
tells me that hypothesis 2 gives the right results again: to come
into being
seems to entail that there is a state at which the entity in question
does not exist, followed by one in which it does, whereas to begin
to
exist seems to indicate an initial time or moment of existence.
I
don't know whether hypothesis 2 is entirely accurate, but it does
seem to be much closer to capturing the meaning of the words than
Craig's hypothesis is.
Another alternative
(say, hypothesis 3) would be just like hypothesis 2 but allowing open
and semi-open finite intervals.
Hypotheses
2 and 3 given the same verdict in daily cases, under either a tensed
or a tenseless theory of time, but there would be a difference in,
say open models of the universe with a metric-finite past, assuming
an intrinsic metric.
In
any case, both alternatives seem to fare much better than Craig's
hypothesis, at least in all the cases tested above - in which both
alternatives 2 and 3 seem to give the right results.
Let's
turn now to the question of whether there are good grounds for
believing that everything that begins to exist has a cause.
William
Lane Craig maintains that the first premise, namely the claim that
everything that begins to exist has a cause, is intuitively clear.
Moreover,
he claims that there is empirical confirmation of that.
He
tries to back up that claim by appealing to our intuitions about
causation - what he calls "metaphysical" intuitions -, and
by bringing up scenarios that purportedly show the absurdity of
denying it, such as, say, horses popping into existence uncaused.
[20]
However,
all of those scenarios would also be a case of denying other
candidates to being intuitive principles, such as the claim that
every event/change of the form "B comes into existence"
- or, more generally, every event/change - has a cause.
In
other words, someone may not accept that everything that begins to
exist has a cause (they don't need to actually deny that everything
that begins has a cause, but simply not affirm it), while accepting
that, for instance, every event/change has a cause; that's
also debatable, but the point is that it's an alternative that avoids
any of the issues raised by Craig, and - at least to me - it seems
more intuitive. That does not mean that one ought to assume that only
events/changes have causes, of course, but that's beside the point.
The
point is that this is an intuitive alternative (though still
debatable), and that none
of the scenarios that Craig brings up - like a horse coming into
existence uncaused - would present any problem for that position,
since that position holds that those events/changes
would
not happen without a cause.
In
any case, a question is: would belief that everything that begins to
exist has a cause be warranted?
Another
one is: is lack of belief in that claim, unreasonable?
Using
Craig's definition of "begins to exist", the issue of
"timelessness" alone is a serious problem: without a good
understanding of what that means, plus good reasons to adopt it,
there appears to be no justification for believing that kind of
principle, even if we assume that the claim is coherent - which
we don't have sufficient reasons to
believe.
In
other words, one ought not to believe it,even
if the assumption that "timeless" (in Craig's usage) is
coherent, were justified.
Moreover,
even if we leave the issue of timelessness aside, there appears to be
no good reason, either intuitive or empirical, to believe that
everything that begins to exist has a cause, either in the sense of
hypothesis 2 , or hypothesis
3, or Craig's hypothesis about the meaning - minus the "timeless"
condition.
Still,
there is no need to settle the matter of what "begins to exist"
mean.
We
can just leave that undefined.
Still,
the question is whether there is support for the claim that anything
has a temporal beginning has a cause - which is what the KCA claims,
after all.
While
it's true that, in daily life,
anything that has a temporal beginning seems to have causes, in daily
life it's also the case that every event/change seems to have causes,
and what is intuitive is may well be that every event - i.e., every
change - has a cause.
So,
two questions are:
Do
we have sufficient reasons for believing not only that every event
has a cause, but that everything that has a temporal beginning even
when no change is involved, has
a cause?
In
other words, do we have sufficient reasons for believing that every X
that begins to exist has a cause, even when there is no change
from a state of affairs at which the
X in question does not exist, to a state at which it does?
Do
we have an epistemic obligation to believe that everything that has a
temporal beginning even when no change is involved, has
a cause?
In
order to assess our intuitions on the matter, we would need to
consider unusual scenarios, such as S1.
I
have to say that I don't have any general intuition that, in such
scenario, B would have a cause.
In
fact, in some scenarios, my intuitions tell me otherwise:
For
instance, in S1, let us stipulate that B is the
universe, or a multiverse, and there is nothing else that exists. Or
let's stipulate that B is an omnipotent being, and let's stipulate
that, at t=0, there are no other beings.
In
those cases, intuitively, I'd say that B begins to exist but may well
not have a cause. At least, I have no intuition that B would have a
cause.
Someone
might protest that I'm constructing scenarios that would be
exceptions to the principle, but the scenarios in question are
counterintuitive and we shouldn't use them as a guide.
However,
in order to construct scenarios in which one could test whether one
has an intuition that every X that begins to exist has a cause,
independently of whether there is an change/event "X comes into
existence", it seems to me one needs precisely to separate
beginning of existence from changes/events - which does not happen in
ordinary cases.
Otherwise,
it could be that what's intuitive to us is just the principle that
every event - that is, any change - has a cause, and the
correlation with a beginning arises because it just happens to be the
case than, in daily life, things that begin to exist are just those X
for which there is an change/event "X comes into existence"
- i.e., a change from a state of affairs at which X does not exist,
to one at which it does.
Of
course, a potentially serious problem may be the reliability of our
intuitions in such cases, but that's no help for someone claiming
that the principle ought to be accepted, or even merely that it's
rational to do so.
In
order to accept something like "everything that begins to exist,
has a cause" as intuitive, one would not only have to lack an
intuition that, in some scenarios, some beings that begin to exist
would probably not have
causes: one would have to have an intuition that those beings would
have causes.
A
possible alternative line of arguing, in support of claim that
everything that begins to exist has a cause, would be to say that if
X begins to exist, then it's clear - either intuitively or
empirically - that there is an change/event "X
comes into being" - i.e., a change from a state of affairs at
which X does not exist, to one at which it does.
However,
there appears to be no intuitive
reason to think that that's always the
case.
In
fact, if time had a beginning (which can't be ruled out on intuitions
alone), it seems more than intuitively clear that there is no event
"time comes into existence": a change from a state of
affairs at which there is no time, to one at which there is time,
seems to be impossible, for reasons similar
to those used to derived a
contradiction earlier.
As
for empirical reasons, someone might try to use objects in daily life
as examples, and claim that everything that begins to exist, also
comes into existence.
But
using objects in daily life as examples might as well be used to
claim that no object is timeless, or that all persons came into
existence, etc., so this avenue does not seem promising for the
theist, either - in any case, they'd have to make their case.
So,
it seems that we're not justified in believing that every X that
begins to exist comes from an event "X begins to exist" -
let alone not justified in not believing it -, or that everything
that has a temporal beginning, has a cause.
It's
true that someone might have different intuitions on the subject, so
that might depend on the person - assuming that we consider those
particular intuitions reliable.
Finally,
someone might raise the issue that cosmologists who worked on the Big
Bang model did not come to the conclusion that they had resolved all
the mysteries and moved on, instead of looking for causes.
However,
it's clear that the model does not provide an understanding of
the universe beyond a certain point, where effects from forces other
than gravity should be taken into consideration.
In
other words, it makes perfect sense that scientists would try to
figure out the causes of a very hot, dense, and small universe that
existed about 13.7 billion years: indeed, we don't know the causes; a
theory that only considers gravity but no other forces is inadequate
to provide a good understanding of it.
But
those scientists seem to be asking the question: "where did that
hot, dense, really small universe come from?" (or similar ones),
on the understanding that before the first state of the
universe that can be analyzed with present-day models, there were
other states that are beyond the descriptive capabilities of current
scientific understanding - states that later changed into a
state that is within said capabilities.
In
other words, they apparently were/are looking for the causes of an
event,
as
well as for a model of how the universe works under conditions not
covered by present-day models.[21]
One
of the arguments that Craig gives in support of the second premise of
the Kalam Cosmological Argument intends to establish that an actual
infinity is metaphysically impossible - though there is no claim of
logical impossibility.
Let's
assess Craig's argument:
William
Lane Craig and J.P Sinclair[22]:
But
now let us imagine a hotel with an infinite number of rooms and
suppose once more that all the rooms are occupied. There is not a
single vacant room throughout the entire infinite hotel. Now suppose
a new guest shows up, asking for a room. “But of course!”
says the proprietor, and he immediately shifts the person in room #1
into room #2, the person in room #2 into room #3, the person in room
#3 into room #4, and so on out to infinity. As a result of these room
changes, room #1 now becomes vacant, and the new guest gratefully
checks in. But remember, before he arrived, all the rooms were
occupied! Equally curious, there are now no more persons in the hotel
than there were before: the number is just infinite. But how can this
be? The proprietor just added the new guest’s name to the
register and gave him his keys – how can there not be one more
person in the hotel than before?
Such questions are
the result of an ambiguity about what it means for there to be “more
persons” in the hotel.
For
instance, if by “more persons” one means “all the
persons who were there remain, and there is at least one who wasn't
there, but now is there”, or if one means that the set of
guests after the new arrival (let's call it “GF1”)
minus the set of guests before the new arrival (let's call it “GI”),
has a greater cardinality than GI
minus
GF1
[23],
then
are are more persons (more precisely, one more) after the new guest
checks in.
On
the other hand, the set of guests in the beginning GI
has
the same cardinality as the set of guests after a new guest arrives,
GF1,
so if by "GF1
has
more persons than GI"
one means that the cardinality of GF1
is
greater than that of G1,
then there are no more persons after the arrival.
That
the sets have the same cardinality only means that there is a
bijection between the two sets, which is not only not
counterintuitive, but is actually obvious:
it's
the same as comparing the set of natural numbers N
(i.e.,
{1, 2, 3, …}), with the set of non-negative integers N0
(i.e., {0, 1, 2, 3,...}).
So,
in the usual mathematical sense of cardinality, N and N0
have the same number of elements, but that only means there is a
bijection between the two (which is, again, obvious, since we can
define F: N0
→ N,
F(k) = (k+1)).
On
the other hand, there is one number in N0
that is not in N
(namely,
0), so in that sense, there is one more element – also, the
cardinality of N0
minus
N is
1, which is greater than the cardinality of N
minus
N0,
which is zero. So, understanding “more elements” in
either of those senses, it is the case that N0
has more elements than N (one more, to be
precise).
The case of the
hotel is no different in that regard; making the example concrete
does not change the fact that any puzzlement arises from the
ambiguity about what's meant by “same number”:
In
the same sense of “same number” in which N0
has the same number of elements as N -
namely, in the sense that there is
a bijection between the two-, the sets of guests after and before the
arrival have the same number of guests.
And
in the two senses I mentioned above in which N0
has one more element than N,
there
is one more guest after the new guest arrived.
If
the example shows something counterintuitive, that's not the actual
infinity, but the infinite hotel
- which
of course we could never build - the practical impossibility of
communicating with infinitely many people at once, etc.
But that does not
appear to be a problem for, say, infinitely many galaxies, or
infinitely many universes (in some sense of “universe”
used in modern cosmology), infinitely many particles, etc.
So, if one explains
what one means by "more", then there is no problem
whatsoever, regardless of whether there is a unique usual meaning of
"more", according to which there are (or there aren't) more
persons after the arrival.
I actually doubt
that only one common meaning of "more" exists, but that is
beside the point.
The point is that
there simply appears to be nothing remotely puzzling here, but merely
a confusion that arises from some ambiguity in what is meant by
"more".
The rest of the
arguments against an actual infinity are based on that ambiguity as
well.
For
instance, Craig expresses some sort of amazement at the alleged
strangeness that even if (denumerably) infinitely
many
more guests arrive, the number of guests is the same as before.[22]
As
in the previous case, there is no puzzlement at all if what's meant
be "same number" is explained:
The
set of guests after the infinitely many (more precisely, ℵ0)
new guests arrive (let's call it GFℵ0
) has all the members of the initial set of guests
GI, and it also has infinitely many guests that GI does
not have.
Also,
GFℵ0
minus GI has infinitely many guests or
members, whereas GI minus GFℵ0
has zero.
On
the other hand, there is a bijection between GI and GFℵ0.
All
that is clear, and there is no puzzlement.
The
question "Are there any more guests?" is not be problematic
once one explains what's meant by "more guests".
It
would be somewhat ambiguous to say that there would never be a single
person more in the hotel than before, as Craig does[22],
but as before, once one clarifies what one is saying, the puzzlement
should disappear: in the usual mathematical sense of cardinality,
there are no more persons, which is to say nothing but that there is
a bijection between the set of guests before the new infinite ones
arrive, and the set of guests after they do arrive.
In the two other
senses I mentioned above, there are more people after the arrival.
All
of this is straightforward, so there should be no need to delve any
further into it: Craig's "Hilbert Hotel"
argument provides no good reason to reach any conclusion about
whether actual infinities exist, or whether or not they're
"metaphysically possible", since it is just the result of
terminological ambiguity and the resulting confusion.
In
addition to the Hilbert
Hotel argument against
an actual infinity, Craig presents other philosophical arguments
against an infinite past on a tensed theory of time -
not against all actual infinities.
Before
I go on, I have to admit that an infinite past on a tensed theory of
time appears counterintuitive to me.
However,
on the other hand, so does a beginning of time!
Counterintuitiveness
aside, the question is whether there are any good reasons to believe
that, on a tensed theory of time, an infinite past is indeed
impossible.
I
used to think that there were - though not for the same reasons as
Craig -, but after further consideration, reading counterarguments,
and so on, I have to admit I can't find such reasons.
To
be clear, I agree that it's impossible, on a tensed theory of time,
to have an infinite past if
there is a first event/change.
Indeed,
if a tensed theory of time is true and there is a first event/change,
then there is no infinite chain of events, one after the other, since
it's impossible to reach an infinity by a finite number of instances
of finite addition.
Moreover,
that is true regardless of whether the events are of equal duration -
assuming an intrinsic metric of time; else, how close they are is a
conventional matter.
One
objection raised against that argument is that it resembles Zeno's
paradoxes.[24]
Craig's
reply to that objection is based on a claim that there are two
crucial differences: the events are of equal duration and actual in
his argument whereas the intervals are potential and unequal in
Zeno's paradoxes.
As
I explained above, the length of the intervals is actually not
relevant. However, that does not seem to work against Craig's
argument in this case: Whatever the solution to Zeno's paradoxes is,
the fact remains that one cannot possibly form an infinity by
finitely adding the number one, or any finite numbers.
Still,
whether or not the arguments resemble Zeno's paradoxes in some way is
not the point here.
Rather,
the point here is whether we have good reasons to believe that an
infinite past is impossible on a tensed theory of time.
I
will argue that at least Craig provides no such good reason. If there
is any, it should be found elsewhere.[25]
One
of Craig's arguments against an infinite past is based on the story
of Tristram Shandy. [26]
Shandy
is a man who writes his autobiography, at a rather slow pace: it
takes Shandy a year to write the events of a single day.
According
to Craig, if Shandy had been writing from infinity, that would lead
to absurdities, and so - as Craig argument goes - we should reject an
infinite past because it's obviously coherent to write an
autobiography at that pace.
However,
Craig does not provide any good reason to believe that it's obviously
coherent - or, indeed, coherent - to write an autobiography at that
rate counting
from infinity.
What
is obviously coherent is to write such an autobiography starting
at a specific day.
Moreover,
there is a good reason why Craig does not provide any good reasons to
believe that it's coherent to write an autobiography at that rate
while having kept that pace 'from infinity': namely, such a deed is
logically
impossible - a
fact that, to my knowledge, was first pointed out by an anonymous
poster who goes by the name "Dante Alighieri".
To
see why this is impossible, let's suppose otherwise, let's suppose
the number of past years has the order type of the non-positive
integers, and let's enumerate the past years in the following way:
[27]
Last
year is 0, the previous year is -1, and so on. For instance, if this
year is 2012, then 2011 is 0, 2010 is -1, 2009 is -2, and so on.
Now,
let F be a function from the set of non-positive integers into itself
such that for all non-negative integers r
and n,
F(-r) = -n if
and only if -n
is the
most recent year Shandy wrote about during the year -r.
For
instance, if, in the year -2000, Shandy wrote about a day in the year
-300001 and about a day in the year -300000, then F(-2000) = -300000.
Given
the rate at which Shandy writes, and given also that, when writing
his autobiography, Shandy never writes about his future, we have the
following conditions:
1)
F(-r) ≤ -r.
2)
F(-r-365) = F(-r) - 1.
By
induction:
3)
F(-r-2*365) = F(-r-365-365) = F(-r-365) - 1=F(-r) - 2
4)
F(-r-k*365) = F(-r) - k, for
all non-negative k.
So,
in particular, taking r=0.
F(-k*365)
= F(0) - k ≤ -k*365.
Hence,
for every natural number k,
5)
364*k ≤ -F(0)
That's
contradictory, as easily seen by taking (for instance) k
= 1 + (F(0)*F(0)).
So,
the Tristram Shandy scenario fails to show that infinitely many past
years are impossible.
Someone
might suggest that precisely the fact that we reach a contradiction
is what should lead us to the rejection of such an infinite past.
However, that would be a confusion, as it should be clear from the
previous proof: what's logically impossible is the scenario itself,
and it's not surprising that absurdities follow from a contradiction,
since everything follows from a contradiction.
Still,
while the proof above should be
enough to debunk the Tristram Shandy
scenario, in case someone is not persuaded by it, let me point out
that the proof in question does not depend on whether a tensed or a
tenseless theory of time is true. But an infinite past seems clearly
logically possible if we assume a tenseless theory of time, just as
an infinite future is.
Also,
somebody might suggest that there might be even more
past years, changing order types,
etc.
However,
that would be beside the point:
The
point here is that the previous proof shows that if the set of past
years is of the same order type as the set of non-negative integers,
the Tristram Shandy case is logically
impossible.
Therefore,
the Tristram Shandy scenario fails to present any challenge to the
possibility of an infinite past in which the set of past years has
the same order type as the set of non-negative integers, and so it
fails to show that infinitely many past years are impossible.
Another
one of Craig's arguments against an infinite past on a tensed theory
of time is based on a scenario involving planets completing
infinitely many orbits.
First,
he claims that somehow it's absurd that if Jupiter completes 2.5
orbits for each one Saturn completes, they would both have completed
the same number, if they have been orbiting the Sun 'from eternity
past'. That would be somehow a "magical" result[28].
Now,
apart from the fact that any planet, star, etc., has a finite
expiration date, the fact is that there is no absurdity at all.
That
the number of orbits is the same if they've been orbiting forever and
there is an infinite past merely means that there is a bijection
between the set of orbits completed by one of the planets, and the
same set for the other planet.
Of
course, again in reality planets
don't
last for that long, but that is not at all relevant.
Indeed,
no one is suggesting that planets
might
do that: we know enough about physics to tell otherwise.
Incidentally,
in any case, the number of orbits completed from
any given time would
be finite, and there would be nothing like Jupiter falling
"infinitely far behind Saturn", or that the "disparity"
has become increasingly greater from
infinite,
etc.: again, there is no beginning from which to count to infinity.
William
Lane Craig:[28]
For
a cardinal number n
is
even if there is a unique cardinal number m
such
that n
=
2m,
and n
is
odd if there is a unique cardinal number m
such
that n
=
2m
+
1. In the envisioned scenario, the number of completed orbits is (in
both cases!) ℵ0, and ℵ0 = 2ℵ0 = 2ℵ0 +
1.
Actually,
using usual mathematical definitions of “even” and “odd”
– and those definitions match common usage of the words -,
integers
are
even or odd, but not transfinite cardinals.
So,
using the words in their usual sense, ℵ0
is neither odd nor even.
Also,
that ℵ0
=
2ℵ0
+
1 only means that there is a bijection between ℵ0
and
(ℵ0
x
{0, 1} U
{1}),
and that ℵ0
=
2ℵ0
only
means that if there is a bijection between ℵ0
and
(ℵ0
x
{0, 1}). But that's all true [29].
Surely,
going by the definition Craig provides, ℵ0
would be both odd and
even, and so would be any other transfinite cardinal, but that is not
at all a problem,
as
long as one keeps in mind what Craig means by the words.
Craig claims that
what he calls the "Standard Hot Big Bang Model" (SHBBM),
supports the second premise of the KCA. He also claims that a tensed
theory of time is true.
W.
L. Craig and J. P. Sinclair[30]
The
standard Hot Big Bang model, as the Friedmann–Lemaître
model came to be called, thus
describes a universe which is not eternal in the past, but which came
into being a finite time ago. Moreover – and this deserves
underscoring – the origin it posits is an absolute origin ex
nihilo. For not only all matter and
energy but also space and time themselves come into being at the
initial cosmological singularity. As Barrow and Tipler emphasize, “At
this singularity, space and time came into existence; literally
nothing existed before the singularity, so, if the Universe
originated at such a singularity, we would truly have a creation ex
nihilo” (Barrow and Tipler
1986, p. 442). On such a model the universe originates ex
nihilo in the sense that it is false
that something existed prior to the singularity.
There
is no good reason to think that we can assume the model to be an
accurate description of the universe beyond a point at which there
was a hot, dense and very small universe - but not
- a singularity of infinite density
(what would that even mean?).
Moreover,
there is no need to add a singular point, even if one keeps
extrapolating backwards in time, nor a way of getting out of the
singularity, so to speak.
However,
let's let all that pass, and let's assume, for the sake of the
argument, that the model Craig offers in support of his arguments is
indeed an accurate portrayal of the early universe.
Then,
under such assumption:
1)
There is a time t(1) in the past, such that the average density d(1)
of the universe at t(1) was greater than the density at a time in the
year 2000 (any time) d(0), so there is a change from a universe with
a density d(1) to a universe with a density d(0).
Thus,
the model entails that there is at least one event/change, E(1),
which happens in semiopen interval [t(1), t(0))
2)
Let's suppose the model entails there are at least k events, E(1),
E(2), E(k), where E(j) happens in the semi-open interval [t(j+1),
t(j)), and 0 < t(j+1) < t(j), for all j between 1 and k.
The
average density of the universe from E(k+1) began to the present day,
is bounded, and so is less than some number d(M).
Since
the model predicts that the density tends to infinity as we
move back in time, there is some time t(k+2), such that 0 < t(k+2)
< t(k+1), and such that d((k+2)) > d(M).
So,
there is a change from a state of the universe with density d((k+2)
to a state of density d, such that d(M) > d > d(k+1), and
that's the event E((k+1)), which happens in the interval [t(k+2),
t(k+1))
Thus,
on this model, there is an infinite temporal regress of events,
which Craig claims is impossible.
Note
that even if the events are increasingly shorter, that would be an
actual infinity under a tenseless theory of time, or under a
growing-block tensed theory.
Craig claims that even on presentism, an infinite regress of events/changes is an actual infinity.
Craig claims that even on presentism, an infinite regress of events/changes is an actual infinity.
If
so, then Craig's "Hilbert Hotel" argument has a false
conclusion.
Furthermore,
according to Craig, this model entails that time has a beginning at
the singularity.
If
so, we could then conclude, on the assumption of this model, that the
universe contains an infinite regress of events with a beginning
point, and so no tensed theory of time is true: even though the
duration of the events is not equal, and even though the sum of all
of the durations is convergent, the fact remains that it's not
possible to get an actual infinity of events by finitely many times
adding a finite number of them (in reality, the model offers no way
out of this "singularity", and adding it is at best
superfluous; without that addition, what we get is a beginningless
series of past events/changes, but that's no better for Craig's
position).
But
what if we drop the assumption that we can extrapolate arbitrarily
back in time, and actually take into consideration the fact that
we're not justified in applying General Relativity to a very small
universe, where forces other than gravity should be taken into
consideration?
In
that case, all we could say is that the universe was in a hot, small,
dense state S1 at some time t over 13 billion years ago, which seems
to have came after a state S2 whose description is beyond
present-day understanding of physics.
So,
the state S2, and the event E(S2,S1): = "The universe
changes from its condition at S2 to its condition at S1" are
both beyond the present-day understanding of physics. And that is
it: There is no suggestion of a beginning of time, or of the
universe, or anything of the sort.
There
is a beginning of the states of the universe whose
description is within the present-day understanding of physics. Of
course, that fact provides no support whatsoever for the second
premise of the Kalam Cosmological Argument, and thus neither does the
"Standard Hot Big Bang Model".
Given
that there
seems to be no sufficient reason to accept the first premise of the
KCA,
then it seems the argument failed.
Still,
assuming that the universe had a beginning and a cause, earlier in
this article, I've analyzed some of the consequences of the
properties assigned by William Lane Craig to the cause of the
universe, showing that a
contradiction is entailed.
In
this section, though, I will let assess mostly other arguments in
which Craig uses conceptual analysis in order to support of some of
the claims about the properties of the cause of the universe, whose
existence is allegedly established by Kalam Cosmological Argument.
[31]
Before
addressing the conceptual claims, I will assess a different one:
According
to Craig, the philosophical arguments in in the KCA show that there
is a first cause, not only a cause of the universe.
In
addition, he claims we ought to posit a single cause, not many,
allegedly due to Occam's razor. [17]
Even
assuming that the KCA succeeded in establishing both a cause of the
universe and a first cause, that would not be a proper use of the
razor:
First,
if we do not know what caused a hot, dense state of the universe that
existed about 13.7 billion years ago, there is no warrant for
believing that it had a single cause, or that that particular cause
was in turn uncaused.
Cosmologists
understand that, and keep trying to find better models - models that
can describe the early universe as well -, rather than assuming that
the hot, dense, early universe was just brought up by a single
uncaused cause, so science can go on.
Second,
even if we knew that something caused the universe, multiverse, etc.
- i.e., that there is a previous cause that does not match, for some
reason, any description used by physics, today or in the future -,
and even if we knew that there is some uncaused cause, there would
appear to be no reason to make any assumptions about the number of
causes of the universe/multiverse, etc., or that said cause or causes
are uncaused. Who knows?
Still,
let's leave that aside for the sake of the argument, and assess the
rest of Craig's arguments for the properties of the cause of the
universe, assuming that said cause would also be the first cause.
Craig
maintains that the first cause must be "changeless", since
an infinite regress of changes cannot exist. [17]
But
if so, then the only thing one can infer from that is that there has
to be a first change.
So,
that is not a problem for even particles: as long as there is a state
and no previous state (hence, no previous change), or for some
kind of field before particles form, etc.; all of that would be
"changeless" in the sense that, well, there is no previous
change.
However
- assuming for now that Craig's claim of changelessness is meaningful
-, Craig seems to mean a lot more than the lack of previous changes
by "changeless", since he claims that the first cause
exists in a state of "absolute changelessness", which [17],
which is allegedly impossible for particles and the like.
But
then, in that case, changelessness does not follow from a lack of
infinitely many past changes, and he incurs a non-sequitur.
In
any event, the point is that no infinite regress of changes only
entails a first change, not a "changeless" state in
whatever sense Craig of "changeless" Craig intends to use
the word.
Moreover,
if the first cause were God, he would change from not knowing any
tensed truths (for instance), to knowing some tensed truths. That's a
change.
Furthermore, as particles, fields, etc., change, God's knowledge of them would, so he would be changing constantly as well.
Furthermore, as particles, fields, etc., change, God's knowledge of them would, so he would be changing constantly as well.
And
if there is a first state in which there are no particles, fields,
etc., God would still change from that state to the next
state, just as any field, etc., in a first state would change from
that state to the next.
On
that note, let's consider the two scenarios
I
introduced earlier: once again, the first cause changes,
just as an object at t=0 would change.
So,
the claim appears to be either contradictory, or meaningless.
Now,
Craig claims is that the first cause is changeless "sans the
universe". [17]
But
once again: what does that even mean?
In
the usual sense of the words, one would understand that an object is
changeless if it does not change as times goes by. But if
there is no time, what does that mean?
So,
in addition to the claim that God is timeless sans creation, and
temporal with creation - which is contradictory,
if
meaningful at all -
Craig adds another mysterious claim - to say the least -, namely that
God is changeless sans the universe.
In
addition, as I pointed out, Craig claims that, since it's changeless,
the first cause is also immaterial.
Leaving
aside potential problems with the concept of "immaterial",
clearly the conclusion is not warranted, as the claim that the cause
is changeless is not warranted, either.
In
earlier
sections,
I
already made
a case against the claim of timelessness of God as the first cause.
In
this subsection, I will briefly recap some of the reasons I've
already given, and then stress the point that even leaving aside any
considerations of durations of the events/changes like 'God changes
from not knowing any tensed facts, to knowing at least one tensed
fact' - or similar ones -, the claim that God is timeless sans
creation but temporal with it is untenable; in this subsection, I
will also consider other potential objections, such as simultaneous
causation and 'timeless will'.
According
to Craig, time cannot exist in the absolute absence of all events -
in other words, in the absolute absence of all changes -, and so the
first cause must be timeless. [17]
However,
as I explained earlier, this purported first cause would change
exactly as an object at t=0 would.
Also,
Craig claims that time has a beginning, so the cause of time must be
timeless.
But
that only highlights
the
problems I just mentioned: for any change/event 'time comes into
existence' would take time,
and
so there would be time before the beginning of time, which is
impossible. And if the event/change were instantaneous, still a
contradiction would follow, for similar reasons as
I argued before.
Using
the word 'timeless' does not avoid that problem: rather, it's just a
misuse of the word "timeless" to describe what is not
ontologically different, making in practice an exception to the claim
that everything that begins to exist, has a
cause.
Someone
might raise the issues of simultaneous causation, or a 'timeless
will' (whatever that is), but that would not block my objections:
First,
in the case of the duration of the events/changes, the issues of
simultaneous causation and a 'timeless will' are orthogonal to the
matter at hand, since a contradiction
can
be derived on other grounds, without making any assumptions about
them.
Second,
leaving the duration of the events/changes aside, let's consider
again the following scenarios, ordering
the states of the world in terms of the direction given by supporters
of the KCA - i.e., the world changes from one state to the next:
First
state of the world.
Timeless
state S. The only object is God, who timelessly wills to create the
universe.
God
exists uncaused.
Second
state of the world.
Temporal
state at t=0.
The
only objects are God and the universe - including, of course, all the
objects in the universe.
God
is the cause of the existence of the universe.
First
state of the world.
Temporal
state t=0. The only object is God, wills to create the universe.
God
exists uncaused.
Second
state of the world.
Temporal
state t=r>0.
The
only objects are God and the universe - including, of course, all the
objects in the universe.
God
is the cause of the existence of the universe.
It
is clear that scenario 4 would contradict a claim that everything
that begins to exist has a cause, at least under common readings of
"begins to exist", and under Craig's.
So,
under those readings, scenario 4 would contradict the first premise
of the Kalam Cosmological Argument. In addition, if there is a claim
that all causation is simultaneous, then scenario 4 would contradict
that as well.
However,
leaving
all of that aside, a more direct and obvious problem is that scenario
3
is
ontologically the same as scenario 4.
In
fact, it's not the case that state S in scenario
3 is
a state of absolute changelessness, whereas the temporal state at t=0
in scenario
4
somehow
changes immediately,
for in both cases, the state changes to the next, and in both cases,
there is no lapse of time during which a state remains unchanged.
So,
in both cases, there is an entity - namely, God - who exists at the
first state of the world, and has a will at that state. God creates
the universe, and changes - coming to know that the universe exists,
for instance -, and that is the case under both descriptions.
However,
this so-called 'timeless' state of God also changes, and in fact
plays exactly
the same role
that
the temporal state at t=0 plays in scenario
4:
So,
the word "timeless" is actually misused,
since there is a false claim that time only starts at the second
state of the world; scenario
4 is
the same as scenario
3,
but without making false claims of timelessness.
Of
course, the same problem arises if one changes the description of the
timeless state in some way - e.g., altering the description of the
"timeless will", etc., since for the same reasons, there is
no ontological difference between the two modified scenarios
-
just a misuse of the word "timeless" in one case.
15.4)
Spacelessness
Since
the claim of timelessness is untenable, this conclusion fails.
But
let's leave that aside for the moment and for the sake of the
argument, and assume that the timelessness claim makes sense. Then,
why can't, say, a multidimensional manifold be timeless? Why some
sort of field?
There
is no need for particles, for instance.
Note that it wouldn't help to say that any field would "immediately" change, make particles, etc., since with the same criterion, any "timeless" object also "immediately" changes, as the previous scenarios show.
Note that it wouldn't help to say that any field would "immediately" change, make particles, etc., since with the same criterion, any "timeless" object also "immediately" changes, as the previous scenarios show.
And
if a field or something like that can be timeless, but can't be
immaterial, then timelessness does not entail immateriality, anyway
(of course, if the so-called "timeless" object were to
change and exist temporally at t=0, that would also entail a
contradiction, but only as it does in the case of God).
According
to Craig, the first cause must be very powerful, since it caused all
of "physical reality" to exist, without any material cause.
[17]
Leaving
aside issues about the concepts of "material", and
"physical", and of course the decisive coherence objections
I explained earlier, the claim that the object in question is very
powerful does not follow from that.
In
other words, given the assumption that some entity is the first cause
of the universe, it might be - purely for example - that the object
in question is only capable of causing things like our universe, and
is incapable of acting within them, or making much of anything else.
Moreover,
it might as well be incapable of changing at all, so it wouldn't be
able to learn anything at all.
Craig
gives three arguments in support of the claim that the first cause is
personal:
Craig
claims that, as Swinburne "points out", there are two kinds
of explanations: personal and scientific. [17]
Of
course, Swinburne argues for that, but the matter is surely
contentious.
Craig
does not defend the distinction, and it would be beyond the scope of
this article to show all that's wrong with Swinburne's claim, but I
will point out that a personal agent acting on some volition can also
be put in terms of a law and some conditions.
For
instance: "If agent A decides X, then X happens", and
"Agent A decides X" would be a way of putting it in such
terms.
If
an agent with a "timeless" volition is posited as a cause
of the universe that is temporal with the universe, and one assumes -
against
good
reasons -
that the claim is coherent, then one might as well posit some
non-personal timeless stuff, with the property that it causes -
deterministically or not - the universe.
There
would be initial conditions too, but - one could say, mirroring the
theist's claims - not initial in a temporal sense, but in the
(mysterious) "timeless" sense in which Craig's deity would
be timeless, and whose coherence I'm assuming in this part of the
article for the sake of the argument.
Another
argument Craig gives is based on the previous "conclusions"
that the first cause is timeless, immaterial, beginningless,
uncaused, and spaceless. [32]
As
I've shown earlier, most of those claims have insurmountable
problems, so this argument fails as well.
The
third avenue Craig takes, in order to support the claim that the
first cause is personal, is based on what he calls "free
agency", and "agent causation". [32]
While
I have no objections to the claim that, say, humans sometimes act on
their own free will, that does not have anything to do with
non-determinism; further, the kind of "freedom" posited by
Craig should not be characterized as "freedom", but more
properly randomness, and randomness surely does not require
agency, or even minds.
But
let's take a look at the matter in more detail:
First,
Craig claims that because the agent is free, he can bring about
things in absence of previously present conditions. [32]
That
clearly is not a good characterization of human freedom.
In
fact, indeterminism in humans has nothing to do with freedom - or
rather, it might get in the way.
To
see this, let's consider the following scenario:
Bob
has been a good police officer for ten years now.
He's
kind, committed to protect and to serve the public, good to his
children, and so on.
Now,
one morning, Bob goes to work as usual. The police get a call about a
domestic disturbance, and Bob and another officer are sent to the
address they're given.
When
they arrive there, they encounter Mary, a fourteen-year old girl high
on drugs, acting completely irrationally. She tells Bob: "You're
a police officer, so you're evil. Why don't you shoot me?".
Bob
has no reason at all to shoot Mary. She poses no threat to him, and
can be easily arrested if needed. Also, Bob is a good person.
However,
it's clear that he has the power to shoot her, and
is free to choose whether to shoot her.
All
he'd have to do is pull his gun, point it at her, and shoot.
No
one would see that coming, so no one could stop him if he did that.
But
Bob - of course - feels no inclination whatsoever to shoot her, does
not shoot her, and follows procedure.
The
point is that saying that Bob can shoot
Mary, that he has the power to
shoot her, that he is free
to choose whether to shoot her, etc., means that he would shoot
her if he chose to
do so, that he's not
being coerced, etc.
It
does not mean
that, even given Bob's mental state at the time he chose to
follow procedure, and even given all the conditions of the world at
that time, it was still possible that Bob would shoot her.
That
can be ascertained by introspection and analysis of the meaning of
the terms.
But
if that is unpersuasive, let's suppose otherwise, and let's assume
that Bob has the kind of "freedom" proposed by
libertarians.
Then,
since Bob could have shot her, but libertarian-freely decided not to
shoot her, it seems that there is a world W with the exact same past
as ours prior to Bob's decision to follow procedure, at which Bob
shot Mary instead.
But
that is not an
exercise of freedom, in the usual sense of the words.
To
see this, let's consider Bob's mental processes leading to his
"decision" to shoot Mary - say, decision D. Bob never
considered shooting her, and had no desire, intention, etc., before
decision D happened.
However,
at some time, his earlier mental processes did not determine his
later mental processes. There is an event "Bob decides to shoot
Mary" that happens irrespective of any previous states of Bob's
mind, and no matter how much Bob would loath being a murderer.
All
of Bob's previous reasoning, desires, behavior, intentions, etc., are
incapable to stop "decision" D from happening. But how's
that Bob's decision?
It
seems D it's not so much a decision Bob made, but rather, it's
something that happened to Bob.
It's not something Bob could have anticipated, or prevented: at some
point his mental processes changed from normal to "shoot Mary",
without forewarning, and without any cause in previous mental
processes.
Someone
might claim that necessarily,
there is always some hidden
reason to shoot people, or to do anything one
can do, but that would have to be argued for, and even then, that
would not change the fact that, in that case, Bob could not have
prevented his mental processes from changing at some point from
normal to "shoot Mary", no matter what he did before - and
that change could not be reasonably said to be his decision,
since he had never considered that before, and the change took him by
surprise.
Those
considerations show that that kind of thing should not be called
"freedom", but more like "an unfortunate kind of
randomness".
That
does not mean that agent non-determinism isn't true.
But
that is surely not required for freedom, and in fact, it might
undermine it, as the previous scenario shows.
Perhaps,
there are situations after which, after assessing the pros and cons,
a human is undecided between A or ¬A; if so, maybe there is a
truly random outcome generator for such cases (which might involve
also several mutually exclusive options: A1, A2, A3,...)
However,
if that is the case, that is not required for free will: a random
generator that delivers 'decisions' in cases in which the mind
remains undecided clearly does not result in more freedom than a mind
that actually makes decisions.
So,
if there is such indeterminism, as long as the indeterministic events
happen when a person is undecided (based on her previous feelings,
desires, reasoning, etc., she is undecided and does not cause any
outcome), maybe that
kind of randomness is compatible
with free will, but that's all.
On
the other hand, if there is an indeterministic feature of human
behavior that happens to be like Bob's example above - i.e., if it
happens against everything
that the person stood for, his previous considerations, etc. -, then,
and as the previous example shows, that kind of indeterminism - at
least, when it happens - would actually preclude free
will; rather, the 'decision' would be an unfortunately random will.
There
is another way to see this, taking into account that even under
the exact same
preexisting conditions - including, of course, the previous mental
states of the libertarian-free agent.
So,
let's consider the following scenario (relativizing time as
required):
Alice
is a libertarian-free human, and at t(s), the state of worlds W and
W' is exactly the same - that includes, of course, Alice's mental
processes.
Later,
Alice libertarian-freely chooses A at W, and B at W', even though the
states of the worlds prior to Alice's decision were the same (A is
different from B).
In
other words, W and W' are exactly the same until Alice's mental
processes diverge.
Now,
let p be a Planck time, and n a non-negative integer, starting with
0.
Let's
consider times t(s)+n*p, and the states of W and W', W(n) and W'(n)
respectively.
Let
n(l) be the last n such that W(n) = W'(n).
Since
the 'decision' was made even given the exact same
prior conditions, it seems that the 'decision' happened between
t(s)+n(l)*p, and t(s)+(n(l)+1)*p = t(s)+n(l)*p+p, in other words, the
decision was made in
not more than a Planck time.
That's
way too fast for any human conscious decision, though. So, it becomes
clearer that the first indeterministic event E that distinguishes
between W and W' is same random alteration of Alice's mental
processes.
And
if previous processes in her mind made E in some sense probable -
assuming that objective probability makes sense -, but weren't enough
to bring it about, something still altered her mind randomly.
And
in those cases in which the improbable
'decision'
happens - i.e., the decision that her previous mental processes made
improbable - we're back with something like the unfortunate case of
Bob, the
libertarian-free police officer.
Someone might
still object that, if such a random change in her mind happened, she
still could have changed her mind, and refrained from carrying out
the decision - in the case of the first
example,
the shooting.
The problem
is, though, that if you can have such a random event between
t(s)+n(l)*p, and t(s)+(n(l)+1)*p, it seems you can have another one
at
every single Planck time that follows, until
the "decision" that was completely against everything the
person previously stood for, actually happens.
But
let's suppose someone introduces some fuzziness in some way - which
they would have to explain, of course; else, the previous reasoning
stands. Even then, the fact would remain that the agent would have a
random component - a change in her mind she can't bring about,
because it happens no matter what she tried previously; it's just
that we wouldn't be able to see that by means of analyzing the
process step-by-step, but all of the other reasons I've given above
remain.
A
theist might say that that's 'actually the agent acting', or
something like that but - whatever that means -, the fact would
remain that that would a partially random agent acting, not one in
which mental processes are sufficient to bring about behavior; it
would be an agent with a randomly altered mind - i.e., a mind that
suffers some alterations that have no sufficient causes; it's akin to
dice-throwing, and in some cases, it might go against everything the
agent had stood for up till then.
So,
for all of the previous reasons, libertarian
free
will ought to be rejected.
That
does not mean we can't act of our own accord, of course. We can have
freedom; it's just that the libertarian account of freedom is the
wrong account.
Second,
humans aside, someone might posit that the first cause is not
deterministic, even though as we saw, indeterminism doesn't have
anything to do with freedom.
But
if the first cause and its "timeless" volition - assuming
coherence in this part of the rebuttal for the sake of the argument,
but against
good
reasons -
aren't sufficient conditions to bring about the universe, then that
only detracts
for
the first cause's power, as he might have failed to bring about the
universe.
As
previous arguments show, Craig's arguments fail to support the
conclusion that there is a first cause, or a cause of the universe,
or that - assuming that there is such a first cause -, the cause has
the properties he claims it has.
But
there is one more point I'd like to address here, and it's about the
meaning of "God":
William
Lane Craig:[33]
5.0.
Therefore, an uncaused, personal Creator of the universe exists, who
sans the universe is beginningless, changeless,
immaterial, timeless, spaceless, and enormously powerful.
This,
as Thomas Aquinas was wont to remark, is what everybody means by
“God.”
Actually,
that is not what everybody means by "God".
It
may not even be what most people mean by "God".
For
instance, Richard Swinburne[34]
means
"a person without a body (i.e., a spirit) who necessarily is
eternal, perfectly free, omnipotent, omniscient, perfectly good, and
the creator of all things".
There
is nothing in Craig's description that entails omnipotence,
omniscience, moral goodness, etc.
Moreover,
Swinburne explicitly denies that timelessness is part of the meaning.
[34]
But
let's take a look at the matter from another perspective:
If
an omnipotent, omniscient, morally perfect creator of all other
beings existed, and moreover he intervened in human history, but he
were not timeless, it would be hard to find many people saying that
God does not exist, on account of a lack of timelessness (assuming
that "timeless" is meaningful, that is).
The
same goes for changelessness.
On
the other hand, if an entity like the one Craig describes existed
(assuming again that the description is coherent),
but - for example - he were not omniscient, not omnipotent, not
morally perfect (or even morally good), and never intervened in human
history - no afterlife, either -, it seems to me that plenty of
people would be inclined to say that God does not exist, without
error.
In
fact, even if the Kalam Cosmological Argument - or, more generally,
any argument - succeeded in showing that the universe has a cause,
and even if further argumentation succeeded in showing that said
cause is an intelligent being with some of the properties Craig
ascribes to him in the previous quotation - or all of them, assuming
they make sense -, that would still not establish that God exists, in
the sense the word "God" is often - perhaps usually - used
by theists, and would be compatible with - for instance - deism.
The arguments made
above show that the KCA provides no support for theism, at least if
either a tensed or a tenseless theory of time is true.
The
results may not cover all interpretations of the premises, or perhaps
uncommon theories of time.
However,
they are quite general, covering not only William Lane Craig's
version of the Kalam Cosmological Argument, but a number of
alternatives as well, including, it seems to me, all the main
possibilities in present-day philosophy.
[0]
Source: William Lane
Craig and J.P. Sinclair, "The Kalam Cosmological Argument",
in "The BlackWell Companion to Natural Theology", Edited by
William Lane Craig and J. P. Moreland, © 2009 Blackwell
Publishing Ltd. ISBN: 978-1-405-17657-6
Page 102.
Page 102.
With
the difference that any statements like “the actual world
contains no state of affairs S at which God exists timelessly”
should be simply ignored if "timeless" is meaningless. But
the main result is the same.
[2]
Source: William Lane
Craig and J.P. Sinclair, "The Kalam Cosmological Argument",
in "The BlackWell Companion to Natural Theology", Edited by
William Lane Craig and J. P. Moreland, © 2009 Blackwell
Publishing Ltd. ISBN: 978-1-405-17657-6
Page 106.
Page 106.
Source:
http://www.reasonablefaith.org/site/News2?page=NewsArticle&id=5673&printer_friendly=1
[4]
The choice of the
change in God from timelessness to temporalness as the event is only
one possibility.
There are
alternatives. For instance, let say the actual world contains a state
of affairs S at which God exists timelessly.
Then, at S, time
does not exist, so it's not the case that God knows that time exists.
On the other hand, at t=0, God knows that time exists.
Let E(1) be the event “God comes to know that time exists”
Let E(1) be the event “God comes to know that time exists”
Another alternative
would be:
At S, there are no
tensed facts. So, it's not the case that God knows any tensed truths.
At t=0, there are tensed facts, so God knows tensed truths. Thus,
God's mind changed - he came to know tensed truths -, and one can
consider the event E(2) “God changes from not knowing any
tensed facts at S, to knowing some tensed facts at t=0”.
On
his website, Craig[7]
says
that it's not clear to him that creation itself is an event which
determines a before and an after.
However,
that E(0) – or, for that matter, E(1), or E(2) [5]–
is
an event follows straightforwardly from the definition of “event”:
an event is any change, and Craig himself says that God changed.
Also, Craig claims
that any event takes time, and a contradiction follows.
In fact, the
definition of "event" is not even needed.
The claim that any
change takes time is sufficient to derive the contradiction.
On that note, let us
suppose the the event E(2) “God changes from not knowing any
tensed facts at S, to knowing some tensed facts at t=0” has
zero duration.
So, at the beginning
of the event, it is not the case that God knows any tensed facts -
since the event is precisely the change in God from not knowing any
tensed facts, to knowing some tensed facts.
On the other hand,
at the end of the event, God does know some tensed facts.
Now, since the event
ends at t=0 and its duration is zero, its beginning is also at
t=0.
Thus, at t=0, God
does not know any tensed facts, and at t=0, God knows some tensed
facts. But that's impossible.
The previous
argument can alternatively be put in the following way: if the change
in God from knowing no tensed facts to knowing at least one tensed
fact is literally instantaneous and occurs at t=0, then at t=0 both
the state from which God changes and the state into which he changes
are present. So, at t=0, it's not the case that God does not know any
tensed facts, and at t=0, God knows at least one tensed fact. But
that is impossible.
Someone might object
that E(2) does not begin at t=0, but at the "timeless state"
S.
However, using the
word "timeless" is not a license to circumvent logic: if
the event ends at t=0, and its duration is literally zero,
then its beginning is also present at t=0 as well.
http://www.reasonablefaith.org/site/News2?page=NewsArticle&id=9069&printer_friendly=1
W.
L. Craig and J. P. Sinclair
In
affirming that things which begin to exist need a cause, the
mutakallim
assumes
the following understanding of that notion, where “x”
ranges
over any entity and “t”
ranges over times, whether instants or moments of nonzero finite
duration:
A.
x begins
to exist at t iff
x comes
into being at t.
B.
x comes
into being at t iff
(i) x exists
at t, and
the actual world includes no state of affairs in which x
exists timelessly, (ii) t
is either the first time at which x
exists or is separated from any t′
< t at
which x existed
by an interval during which x does
not exist, and (iii) x’s
existing at t is
a tensed fact.
Source: William Lane
Craig and J.P. Sinclair, "The Kalam Cosmological Argument",
in "The Blackwell Companion to Natural Theology", Edited
by William lane Craig and J. P. Moreland; pages 184, 185.
[9]
Later,
I will consider alternative
readings of "begins to exist",
showing that alternative versions of the KCA based on them provide no
support for theism, either.
[10]
Someone
might not accept the claim that, on a tensed theory of time, the fact
of temporal becoming alone - i.e., the passage of time - counts as a
change.
According
to such a view, even if there were infinitely many times t(n+1) <
t(n), for all n, without any change in any entity, that would not be
enough to establish that there are infinitely many past
events/changes.
There
is no need to settle that matter here, since in this case, by
assumption, God
exists
at t and at u < t, and that entails an event, as I show in section
three.
[11]
Since,
for every two times u < t, one can consider the event E(u,t): “God
comes to know that u is past, and t is present”, it follows
that for every two points in time, there is a corresponding event.
Since,
on a tensed theory of time, there can't be infinitely many events
between two given points, then it follows that there can't be
infinitely many points in time between two given points in time.
In
other words, on a tensed theory of time, there cannot be infinitely
many events, one after the other, in a closed temporal interval
[t1,t2].
Thus,
given the God assumption, such an interval can't contain infinitely
many instants, either.
It
follows that time is discrete, not continuous.
By
"in the context of the KCA" I mean that I make no claim
here as to whether something provides support for theism in other
contexts - i.e., whether something would support an argument for
theism different from the KCA, in any of its versions.
Such
a claim would far exceed the scope of this article.
[13]
Here,
"x"is just as in Craig's hypothesis - i.e., it can be any
being -, and 0 ≤ t1 ≤ t2.
As
for the interval [t1,t2], an interval seems to be required because
otherwise, there might be a problem in cases of vagueness: e.g.,
there may not be a specific instant t such that the Moon existed at
t, but at no u < t: the word "Moon" may be too vague for
that.
That
also seems to be in line with common speech: when we say that
something began on a day, or a year, etc., we're considering
intervals, not instants. Even when we speak in terms of seconds, or
millisecond, we're speaking in terms of intervals, even if very short
ones.
Source:
William Lane Craig and J.P. Sinclair, "The Kalam Cosmological
Argument", in "The BlackWell Companion to Natural
Theology", Edited by William Lane Craig and J. P. Moreland, ©
2009 Blackwell Publishing Ltd. ISBN: 978-1-405-17657-6; page 183.
[16]
Source:
William Lane Craig and J.P. Sinclair, "The Kalam Cosmological
Argument", in "The BlackWell Companion to Natural
Theology", Edited by William Lane Craig and J. P. Moreland, ©
2009 Blackwell Publishing Ltd. ISBN: 978-1-405-17657-6
Page 192.
Page 192.
Source:
William Lane Craig and J.P. Sinclair, "The Kalam Cosmological
Argument", in "The BlackWell Companion to Natural
Theology", Edited by William Lane Craig and J. P. Moreland, ©
2009 Blackwell Publishing Ltd. ISBN: 978-1-405-17657-6; page 184.
[19]
Source:
William Lane Craig and J.P. Sinclair, "The Kalam Cosmological
Argument", in "The BlackWell Companion to Natural
Theology", Edited by William Lane Craig and J. P. Moreland, ©
2009 Blackwell Publishing Ltd. ISBN: 978-1-405-17657-6; page 182.
[21]
That aside, let me
stress that adopting the view that all events have causes does not
require one to adopt the view that only events have causes, and not
adopting the view that everything that begins to exist has a cause
does not require one to adopt the view that some things that begin to
exist have no causes.
[22]
Edited
by William lane Craig and J. P. Moreland; page 109.
[23]
By
“Set A minus set B” I mean the set C whose elements are
all the elements that are in A, but are not in B.
Source:
William Lane Craig and J.P. Sinclair, "The Kalam Cosmological
Argument", in "The BlackWell Companion to Natural
Theology", Edited by William Lane Craig and J. P. Moreland, ©
2009 Blackwell Publishing Ltd. ISBN: 978-1-405-17657-6.
Page
119.
Of
course, the KCA would still fail for some the other reasons explained
in this article, even if all
of
Craig's arguments against an infinity were successful. But I'm trying
to be thorough.
Source:
William Lane Craig and J.P. Sinclair, "The Kalam Cosmological
Argument", in "The BlackWell Companion to Natural
Theology", Edited by William Lane Craig and J. P. Moreland, ©
2009 Blackwell Publishing Ltd. ISBN: 978-1-405-17657-6
Pages
120-124
I'm
stipulating 1 year = 365 days and ignoring leap years, for the sake
of simplicity; a more complicated proof would include leap years, but
it's clear that the contradiction does not depend on whether we count
leap years.
Source:
William Lane Craig and J.P. Sinclair, "The Kalam Cosmological
Argument", in "The BlackWell Companion to Natural
Theology", Edited by William Lane Craig and J. P. Moreland, ©
2009 Blackwell Publishing Ltd. ISBN: 978-1-405-17657-6
Page
120.
Incidentally,
it seems that the 'planets' argument also fails to distinguish
between a tensed and a tenseless theory of time.
I'm
using the definition of the cardinal of an ordinal n
as
the least ordinal m
that
can be put in a one-to-one correspondence with n
(ordinals
are sets, and so are cardinals), but that's not important here. The
relevant point is that there is no absurdity or counterintuitive
result, once one takes into consideration what the words actually
mean.
Source:
William Lane Craig and J.P. Sinclair, "The Kalam Cosmological
Argument", in "The BlackWell Companion to Natural
Theology", Edited by William Lane Craig and J. P. Moreland, ©
2009 Blackwell Publishing Ltd. ISBN: 978-1-405-17657-6; page 130.
Source:
William Lane Craig and J.P. Sinclair, "The Kalam Cosmological
Argument", in "The BlackWell Companion to Natural
Theology", Edited by William Lane Craig and J. P. Moreland, ©
2009 Blackwell Publishing Ltd. ISBN: 978-1-405-17657-6
Pages 191-194.
Pages 191-194.
Source:
William Lane Craig and J.P. Sinclair, "The Kalam Cosmological
Argument", in "The BlackWell Companion to Natural
Theology", Edited by William Lane Craig and J. P. Moreland, ©
2009 Blackwell Publishing Ltd. ISBN: 978-1-405-17657-6
Page 193.
Page 193.
Source:
William Lane Craig and J.P. Sinclair, "The Kalam Cosmological
Argument", in "The BlackWell Companion to Natural
Theology", Edited by William Lane Craig and J. P. Moreland, ©
2009 Blackwell Publishing Ltd. ISBN: 978-1-405-17657-6
Page 194.
Page 194.
[34]
Clarendon
Press Oxford.
Page
7.
No comments:
Post a Comment